Protection of Conscience Project
Protection of Conscience Project
www.consciencelaws.org
Service, not Servitude

Service, not Servitude

World Medical Association
Revision of WMA Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion (2006)

Appendix "E"

Therapeutic and Elective Abortion


E1.    A critical distinction

E1.1    Alone among the WMA members responding to the Secretariat Revision, the Royal Dutch Medical Association clearly distinguished between therapeutic abortion and elective abortion and suggested that the distinction should be openly acknowledged. 

The Royal Dutch Medical Association agrees that physicians can't be forced to perform an abortion. There are little situations in which abortion is therapeutic and those situations are mostly not controversial. Therefore we suggest to speak about elective abortion instead of therapeutic abortion. (Emphasis added) (Appendix "B," B2.5.2)

E1.2    In other words, the Dutch believed that a policy was needed on "elective" abortion because "elective" abortion is controversial.

E1.3    The distinction was recognized by Norway, which asserted that women have a right to elective abortion. (Appendix "B", B2.4.1)

E1.4    The distinction was implicit in Denmark's recommendation that "therapeutic abortion" should be defined (Appendix "B", B1.1, Comment)

E1.5    France did not mention elective abortion. However, its emphatic insistence that the policy should be understood to refer exclusively to "Therapeutic Interruption of Pregnancy or Interruption of Pregnancy on Medical Grounds" makes sense only if it is understood that abortions can be provided for non-therapeutic or non-medical reasons. (Appendix "B", B2.8.1)

E1.6    An unknown number of Associate Members believed that to delete the word "therapeutic" from the policy would be a "major change," and that there should be two documents: one for "therapeutic" abortion and one on "legal" abortion, clearly implying that, in countries where abortion is legal, it is not necessarily "therapeutic." (Appendix "B", B2.3.1)

E2.    "Therapeutic" abortion

E2.1    The British response provided the clearest indication of what is meant by "therapeutic" abortion: an abortion performed "to save the life or prevent grave permanent injury to a pregnant woman." (Appendix "B,"B2.7.4) This definition is consistent with the legal and medical understanding of "therapeutic" abortion that prevailed at least in common law countries following the decision of The King v. Bourne in 1938.73 The rule taken from Bourne informed the Code of Ethics of the Canadian Medical Association until the Code was changed following abortion law reform in Canada (Appendix "D", D1.1). Abortion was held to be legally justified to preserve the life of the mother, but the judge in Bourne instructed the jury that they should take a "reasonable view" of this.

It is not contended that those words mean merely for the purpose of saving the mother from instant death. . . [W]here the doctor anticipates, basing his opinion upon the experience of the profession, that the child cannot be delivered without the death of the mother, it is obvious that the sooner the operation is performed the better. The law does not require the doctor to wait until the unfortunate woman is in peril of immediate death.74

He later added that an abortion could be justified if continuing the pregnancy would probably "make the woman a physical or mental wreck."75

E2.2    That the British understood "therapeutic" abortion to be a procedure connected with the preservation of the life of the mother is also reflected in their recommendation (adopted verbatim in WGAP Clause 9) that no woman should lose her life "because therapeutic abortion services are unavailable." (Appendix "B", B2.7.6)

E2.3     This understanding of "therapeutic" abortion is consistent with French insistence that a "Therapeutic Interruption of Pregnancy or Interruption of Pregnancy on Medical Grounds" must be preceded by consultation with (and presumably the approval of) experts. It also explains why the French considered it a "medical act" that precludes conscientious objection, yet maintained the right of physicians to withdraw based upon their "convictions." They could not imagine how a physician could "conscientiously" refuse to intervene to prevent a woman from dying or suffering "grave permanent injury," but could understand that a physician might refuse to participate for reasons of professional judgement (i.e., clinical convictions).

E3.    "Elective" abortion

E3.1    The Royal Dutch Medical Association provided a satisfactory definition of "elective" abortion when it recommended that reference to mother and unborn child be replaced with the statement, "A pregnant woman may consider terminating her pregnancy for medical or other reasons."(Appendix "B", B2.5)

E3.2    Notice that"other reasons" is unrestricted; it includes any non-medical reason. It could include sex selection or a decision to break a surrogacy contract, for example. On the other hand, while this concedes that a woman may consider an abortion for any non-medical reason, it does not concede that a physician is obliged to provide an abortion for a non-medical reason. There is, in practice, a difference between abortions women "may consider" and abortions physicians are willing to provide. This appears to explain why the Dutch believed that the WMA should have a policy on elective abortion.

E3.3    While abortions performed for socio-economic or other non-medical reasons are clearly elective, some abortions provided for ostensibly medical reasons can also be classed as elective, including abortions used as a method of birth control.

E4.    "Therapeutic" vs. "medically indicated" abortion

E4.1    The decision of the Working Group to replace the term "therapeutic" with "medically indicated" does not resolve the issue raised by the distinction between therapeutic and elective abortion, and its added references to "evidence-based medicine" and "good clinical practice" are not helpful. On the contrary: these revisions may confuse things further.

E4.2    As the Royal Dutch Medical Association observed, therapeutic abortions are very rare. However, contraception is generally considered to be "medically indicated" according to "evidence-based medicine" and "good clinical practice" even if actually prescribed solely for socio-economic reasons. Thus, if contraception fails, elective abortions will probably be considered "medically indicated" for the same reasons contraception was prescribed, whether or not continuation of the pregnancy would actually endanger the woman's life or health.

E4.3    As a result, it seems likely that, in countries like Canada, the United States and the United Kingdom, almost all abortions are elective birth control procedures performed for socio-economic reasons. When this occurs, "medically indicated" usually means nothing more than that the procedure is one that requires technical competence normally possessed only by trained physicians and healthcare workers.

E4.4    On the other hand, "medically indicated" may have a medical (though non-therapeutic) meaning in some situations, as when eugenic abortions are justified by reference to desirable or undesirable characteristics of progeny, or when sex-selective abortion are refused as "not medically indicated." As the two examples illustrate, this application of the term is not without controversy.

E4.5    In contrast, where therapeutic abortion is the norm, "medically indicated" according to "evidence-based medicine" and "good clinical practice" will be understood to refer specifically to the need to preserve the life of a woman or (as the British stated) to prevent grave and permanent injury to her.

E4.6    Thus, "therapeutic" and "medically indicated" are not equivalent terms. "Medically indicated" can refer to both therapeutic and elective abortions. The WGAP would, if adopted, mean quite different things in different parts of the world, especially since the wording of the critical section of the document is ambiguous on this point.(Appendix "C", C2.3.13).

E5.    Abortion for birth control

E5.1    In developed countries like Canada, the United States and the United Kingdom, where abortion is legal and widely available, though abortion is not the primary method of birth control, the number of elective abortions for birth control is overwhelmingly greater than the number of therapeutic abortions.

E5.2    For example, during the eleven years from 1956 to 1967, Canadian physicians performed 300 abortions to preserve the life of the mother in accordance with the Bourne criteria,76 about 0.05% of all live births.77 This reflects the Royal Dutch Medical Society (RDMS) comment about therapeutic abortions: "There are little [i.e., "few"] situations in which abortion is therapeutic and those situations are mostly not controversial." (Appendix "B," B2.5.2)

E5.3    As soon as the new Canadian abortion law went into effect, the number of abortions increased exponentially, from under 300 in eleven years to more than 11,000 in the first year.78 The Canadian Medical Association approved abortion for "non-medical social grounds" in 1971,79 and by 1974 it had become clear that most abortions were being performed for "non-medical - social, psycho-social or socioeconomic - reasons."31 By 1976 the abortion rate was 14.9% of live births: almost 30 times higher than the therapeutic abortion rate prior to the change in the law.80 Assuming the therapeutic abortion rate remained at the pre-reform level, it appears that 99.95% of abortions in Canada in 1976 were elective procedures performed for the purpose of birth control.

E5.5     However, recognition that abortion is used primarily as a method of birth control has been obscured by the legal framework established as part of abortion law reform. All abortions - including the 99% that were elective - were officially deemed "therapeutic," because Canadian criminal law ostensibly permitted abortion only to preserve the "life or health" of the mother.81 The enormous increase in elective abortions was made possible simply by adopting the World Health Organization definition of health: "a state of complete mental, physical and social well-being."82 A similarly broad definition is used by the World Medical Association.83

E6.    Abortion for birth control and "reproductive rights"

E6.1     That abortion in North America and Britain is primarily used for birth control has been corroborated by the British Pregnancy Advisory Service,84, 85 and the U.S. Supreme Court.86

E6.2     It is also corroborated by the arguments of prominent reproductive rights advocates. For example, Canadian law professor Daphne Gilbert asserts that women have a right to "reproductive autonomy,"87 even a constitutional right to "reproductive autonomy,"88 which, in fact, means a constitutional right to something that is manifestly impossible. More reasonably, her concern is to ensure that women have "access to reproductive services,"89 described variously as "reproductive health care,"90 "reproductive health services"91 and "reproductive care."92 Such services, she argues, are essential for a woman's "reproductive health."93 Hence, women have "reproductive rights,"94 which include a right to make "reproductive health choices"95 that foster their "reproductive control."96

E6.3     Her frequent references to medical services, care or treatment97 and concern expressed about refusal to offer or denial of medical services98 all occur within this context. While generic reference to "reproductive" rights or "reproductive" health care is broad enough to include obstetrics, gynaecology, fertility treatments and assisted reproductive technology, Gilbert is exclusively concerned with abortion and contraception.99 Within the context of her paper, "reproductive services" means abortion and contraception, without distinction.

E6.4     What she asserts is simply a freestanding right to birth control (by any means) and a corresponding obligation on the part of physicians to provide it. From her "reproductive rights" perspective, there is no relevant moral or legal difference between abortion and contraception, and it is immaterial whether birth control is achieved by surgery (abortion or sterilization, though the latter is not mentioned), by drugs (contraceptives or abortifacients) or by devices (diaphragms or IUDs).

E6.5     Of particular interest, though Gilbert argues within the context of "reproductive health" (as she understands it), her focus is on birth control for the purpose of safeguarding "earning capacity," choice of "life options" and "life's course," participation in "economic and social life," an ability to reach one's"full potential," aspiration to "equal citizenship stature," and "dignity and worth." Without birth control, she argues, women may face "nine months of unwanted pregnancy," "economic and social costs of child-bearing" and "the potential imposition of a lifetime of child care obligations."100

E6.6     Granted the validity of these interests, none of the reasons Gilbert offers to compel physicians to provide birth control (by elective abortion or other means) reflect a therapeutic paradigm. Indeed, in her sole reference to therapeutic abortion, she concedes the point made by the Royal Dutch Medical Association: abortions needed to save the life of a woman are rare, and conscientious objection less likely in such circumstances.101

E7.    Abortion and other forms of birth control distinguished

E7.1    The fact that only women have abortions is sometimes raised to ground a claim for sex discrimination. It is easy to leap to that conclusion as long as one does not advert to the specific nature of the act to which terms like "reproductive service" and "abortion" are applied.

E7.2    Elective abortion, as most commonly practised, is the killing of a human embryo (after implantation) or unborn child/fetus for the purpose of birth control, or, as Gilbert would have it, for the purpose of ensuring the "reproductive control" of women. Where this is legal, one human individual is permitted to deliberately and unilaterally direct the killing of a different human individual without even the possibility of the consent of the individual being killed. That is the fundamental structure of the act.  It is reasonable to incorporate this fact into one's moral reasoning.

E7.3    That the embryo/fetus/unborn child killed by abortion is a member of the human species is an objective and empirically verifiable fact, even if the law denies the individual killed the status of "human being" or "person" (understood legally as a "rights holder"). It is also  reasonable to incorporate this fact into one's moral reasoning.

E7.4    Medical and surgical abortion involve the killing of an embryo/fetus/unborn child, and this clearly distinguishes elective abortion from other forms of birth control. For this reason, many physicians may be willing to provide or refer for all forms of birth control except abortifacients and abortions. Even then, they may be willing to provide or refer for therapeutic abortions.102 This clearly demonstrates that they are motivated by ethical concern about the procedure rather than making distinctions based on prohibited grounds of discrimination.

E7.5    In the Project's experience, physicians who, for reasons of conscience, refuse to kill a human individual by abortion do not refuse because a woman makes the request or gives the order. They would also refuse to kill a human individual if asked or ordered to do so by a man. The sex or status of the person who gives the order to kill is not relevant to their moral or ethical decision-making. It is influenced, instead, by consideration of their moral obligations to the individual whom they are directed to kill.

E7.6    The killing of her embryo/fetus/unborn child may be particularly important or advantageous for the woman making the request, and the law may not permit an inquiry into her reasons. The law may simply assume that they are sufficient to justify her decision to ask or direct someone to do the killing, or to provide the means for her to do the killing herself. It does not follow, however, that reasons a woman finds sufficient to justify her own acts are sufficient to justify the acts of others, let alone to compel others who think differently to kill another human individual, or to punish them if they refuse.

E8.    Abortion and personal integrity

E8.1    Those who would suppress physician freedom of conscience with respect to abortion frequently assert that physicians must act according to the interests of a woman as she understands them because pregnancy and childbirth have a profound impact on her, but physcians are unaffected by it.

E8.2    Pregnancy, abortion and childbirth all profoundly engage a woman's bodily integrity, her right to control her own body, and security of the person. Pregnancy may be accompanied by bouts of nausea and other medical issues, including risks of various kinds. Nine months gestation includes nine months of gradually increasing discomfort for the mother. Labour is usually painful. There is no doubt that a woman's bodily and personal integrity and security are inseparably involved with the conception, gestation and birth of a child.

E8.3    However, it is a mistake to assert that only the bodily integrity of the woman need be considered, that only her security of the person is relevant, or that only her right to control her own body is at stake. The bodily integrity of an objecting physician is equally at stake. Just as a mother's womb is essential for the life of a fetus, so a physician's hands and skills are essential for killing the fetus.

E8.4    If one agrees that a woman must not be compelled to use her womb to sustain the life of a fetus because she has the right to control her own body, it would seem to follow that objecting physicians must not be compelled to use their hands to kill a fetus, since they also have the right to control their own bodies. The argument applies equally to every other act that requires the use of a physician's body, such as writing a prescription or arranging an effective referral.

E8.5    Granted a woman's personal integrity is inseparable from her bodily integrity and moral agency, so, too, is a physician's personal integrity inseparable from his bodily integrity and moral agency.

E9.    "Therapeutic" and "elective" abortions and freedom of conscience

E9.1    Attempts to suppress physician freedom of conscience with respect to abortion frequently assume the paradigm of "therapeutic" abortion. That is: it is said that physicians must be compelled to provide or refer for abortions in order to save women's lives or to prevent serious, permanent injury to them. This is the premise underlining the WGAP demand for referral.

E9.2    However, the premise is demonstrably false in the vast majority of cases. As the Royal Dutch Medical Association observed, such situations are extremely rare and generally uncontroversial (E1.1). This is not surprising, since, in such cases, physicians who generally object to abortion may well be willing to refer for the procedure.

E9.3    Comments on this point from the Netherlands, Norway, Denmark and France should have alerted the Working Group to the need to distinguish between elective and therapeutic abortion before attempting to address the issue of physician freedom of conscience. The distinction is critical because a physician's ethical and professional obligations to provide elective procedures cannot be reasonably construed as being identical to their obligations to provide emergency medical treatment. It is disingenuous to purport to "balance" physician freedom of conscience with patient access to abortion without taking this into account.

E9.4    Unfortunately, the Working Group not only ignored or failed to note this distinction, but replaced the existing protection of conscience provision with a passage that is ambiguous on this very point (C2.3.13). This is likely to cause more confusion and controversy.