Canadian/Royal Dutch Medical Association Proposed Change to WMA Policies
Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide
Full Text
VI. CONTENTS OF THE CMA/RDMA PROPOSAL
VI.1 Introduction
VI.1.1 The focus of this review is the 2018
proposal by the CMA and RDMA (2018C/RDMA),1 but a comparison with the
original proposal (2016C/RDMA)2 is
sometimes necessary to fully grasp the implications of the most recent
document. Three parts of the proposal that warrant attention are
outlined below, with some preliminary observations. Detailed analysis follows in
Part VII.
VI.2 Related WMA policies
VI.2.1 The CMA and RDMA state that the only WMA policies
related to their proposal are the WMA Resolution on Euthanasia, the
WMA
Declaration on Euthanasia, and the WMA Statement on Physician Assisted
Suicide, which their proposal would replace.
VI.2.2 However, existing WMA policies against euthanasia
and assisted suicide are cited and emphatically applied in the WMA
Declaration of Venice on Terminal Illness3 and the WMA
Declaration on End-of-Life Medical Care.4 It
appears that the CMA and RDMA overlooked these declarations in drawing up
their proposal.
VI.2.3 If the WMA accepts the C/RDMA proposal
it will also have to revise these declarations, either by deleting all references
to euthanasia and assisted suicide, or by identifying them as services
physicians may wish to provide where they are legal.
VI.3 Preamble
VI.3.1 Irrelevant or uncontroversial assertions
VI.3.1.1 The CMA and RDMA note that the progress of modern
medicine has generated difficult questions about the usefulness and
appropriateness of medical interventions (2018C/RDMA §5). This is irrelevant. Problems caused by
therapeutic obstinacy - unwanted, disproportionate, futile or overly aggressive medical treatments
- can be solved without recourse to euthanasia or assisted suicide, and the
solutions do not impose any obvious burdens upon physician freedom of
conscience.
VI.3.1.2 The first two sentences of
2018C/RDMA §7 do not
invite or support the conclusion that the WMA should change its policy
against euthanasia or assisted suicide, nor do they impose any burdens upon
physician freedom of conscience:
-
Appropriate end-of-life care should routinely
respect and promote patient autonomy and shared decision-making, and be
respectful of the values of the patient and his or her family.
-
Physicians must also focus on quality of care, and
on the choices that can be made together with their patients as they
near their end of lives.
VI.3.2 Rights claims
VI.3.2.1 The sole justification offered in the Preamble
for changing WMA policy against physician participation in euthanasia and
assisted suicide is found in the last sentence of
C/DMA2018 §7:
Patients must be free to decide for
themselves what treatments they want and the manner and circumstances of
their death and may not be forced to die in ways they would not wish.
(Emphasis added)
VI.3.2.2 There is no dispute that
patients have at least a legal right to refuse treatment that they do not
want. While they are free to decide what treatments they
want, it does not follow that they have a right to have treatments
they want, but the distinction is elided in the statement, and it is not
clear that it is recognized. In any case, these are essentially
autonomy-based rights claims ("must'): that patients have a right to choose
(and perhaps access) any treatment they do want, a right to determine the manner
and circumstances of their death, and, finally, a right not to die "in ways
they would not wish" - from natural causes, for example.
VI.3.2.3 These rights claims are contested
and have serious implications for physician freedom
of conscience, as Dr. Blackmer and then CMA President Dr. Louis Hugo
Francescutti admitted when they announced the CMA's intention to intervene
in the Carter case:
[W]e must recognize that decisions taken at the end
of life are not made in a vacuum. They affect family members, loved ones,
caregivers, healthcare providers … and even physicians. One person’s right
is another person’s obligation, and sometimes great burden. And in this
case, a patient's right to assisted dying becomes the physician’s
obligation to take that patient’s life. (Emphasis added)5
VI.3.3 Assertion of need
VI.3.3.1 The Preamble notes that in jursidictions that have legalized physician assisted suicide
and/or euthanasia, "some physicians" provide
the services "to help meet the immediate needs of their patients, in order to
alleviate intractable and hopeless suffering." (2018C/RDMA §1) The original proposal (2016C/RDMA
§2) said nothing of "needs," noting only that EAS practitioners
were motiviated by "compassion."
VI.3.3.2 The change implies an objectively verifiable
need to be killed
or helped to commit suicide to address pain or suffering. By approving the policy the WMA would
acknowledge such a need, and, implicitly, a corresponding obligation on the
part of physicians.
VI.3.3.3 Those opposed to euthanasia and assisted suicide
would contest the assertion that euthanasia or assisted suicide
are actually requested and provided only to "alleviate intractable
and hopeless suffering." Some prominent cases suggest that the range of
what is said to constitute "intractable and hopeless suffering" is
extraordinarily broad.6,7,8
VI.3.3.4 In any case, it will be seen presently that the CMA and RDMA do not hold
that euthanasia and assisted suicide should be provided only in cases of
intractable and hopeless suffering, so the reference to intractable and hopeless suffering in the preamble
is actually of no consequence.
VI.3.4 Conflict between euthanasia/assisted suicide and medical practice
VI.3.4.1 The Preamble acknowledges that euthanasia and assisted suicide challenge (it
does not say contradict) the traditional concepts (it does not say ethics) of the
medical profession, and that the practices are not part of the "traditional
role" of physicians (2018C/RDMA §8).
VI.3.4.2 Even in countries where there is an appetite for euthanasia and
assisted suicide and the procedures are legal, the majority of physicians
who cannot reconcile the procedures with their ethical commitments is a very
large majority indeed. In Belgium, only about 1% of all physicians
participated in euthanasia in the first year; for the next three years only
about 2% were involved. 13 years after legalization less than 14% of Belgian
physicians were providing the service.9 The Netherlands began with much higher rates once euthanasia was
formally legalized, but twelve years later the proportion of all physicians
providing euthanasia was still less than 10%.10
Less than 1% of all physicians prescribe assisted suicide drugs in Oregon11
and Washington state,12 though assisted
suicide has been legal in those jurisdictions for nine and almost 20 years
respectively. These are maximum estimates; actual numbers could be much
lower, because one practitioner may be responsible for a number of cases.13
Four or five euthanasia cases per year is apparently considered a
responsible maximum for a euthanasia practitioner in the Netherlands.14
Applying the Netherlands rule of thumb, the 551 Ontario patients who died by
euthanasia or assisted suicide in the first year of practice15
could have been adequately serviced by roughly 110 to 137 practitioners
willing to personally administer the lethal drugs - or about 0.4% of active
Ontario physicians.16
VI.3.4.3 These statistics are approximations, but,
combined with the results of the WMA regional conferences, they amply
demonstrate that the overwhelming majority of physicians worldwide do not
wish to be involved in euthanasia and assisted suicide. It is thus noteworthy that the 2016 admission that "the majority of physicians" find the procedures to be
irreconcilable with medical ethics (2016C/RDMA §7) has been struck out entirely, replaced in 2018 with the statement that "many physicians" merely
recognize the conflict (2018C/RDMA §8).
VI.3.4.4 Arguments concerning
coerced referral for abortion can be retooled and applied to euthanasia, and
disputes concerning compulsory referral for euthanasia reflect long-running
disputes about compulsory referral for abortion. The connection is
demonstrated by the importation of two passages from the current revision of
the Declaration of Oslo into the C/RDMA proposal. The first
concerns ethical conflict about abortion and euthanasia/assisted suicide (IV.6.5):
MEC 209/Therapeutic Abortion REV4/Apr2018
|
MEC 210/Euthanasia and
PAD/Oct2018
|
3. A circumstance where the patient may be harmed by
carrying the pregnancy to term presents a conflict between the life
of the foetus and the health of the pregnant woman.
Diverse responses to resolve this dilemma
reflect the diverse cultural, legal, traditional, and regional
standards of medical care throughout the world.
|
8. . . . euthanasia and physician assisted death for many
physicians present a conflict between respecting human life and
alleviating suffering. Diverse responses to resolve this dilemma
reflect the diverse cultural, legal, traditional, and regional
standards of medical care throughout the world.
|
VI.2.4.5 In fact, as the regional meetings demonstrated, the responses are not
diverse but sharply dichotomous. The CMA and RDMA hold what is actually
an outlying minority position.
VI.3.5 Palliative care not a prerequisite for euthanasia/assisted suicide
VI.3.5.1 A comparison of the 2016 and 2018 documents is
especially instructive in relation to palliative care. Originally said
to be part of "part of good and appropriate medical care" (2016C/RMDA §5),
in the revised proposal this is only so when it is "available" (2018C/RMDA §6).
The implication may be that actual access to palliative care need not be a
precondition for the provision of euthanasia and assisted suicide, a
conclusion consistent with the proposal's recommendations.
VI.4 Recommendations
VI.4.1 The WMA Statement on Physician Assisted Suicide
declares that euthanasia and assisted suicide are unethical, "must be
condemned by the medical profession," and that physicians providing the
services act unethically. Thus, according to current WMA policy, the CMA and
RDMA have not only failed in their professional duty to condemn the
practices, but are acting unethically by supporting euthanasia/assisted
suicide providers. The CMA wants the WMA to reverse its position.17
VI.4.2 To accomplish this, the CMA and RDMA recommend that the WMA
make four policy statements.
VI.4.3 The WMA does not support/does not condemn
VI.4.3.1 2018C/RDMA §9 is the first and principal policy statement. The core element is very similar to the resolution used by the
CMA Board of Directors as the basis for reversing CMA policy
against euthanasia and assisted suicide.
The final sentence in 2018C/RDMA §9 has been taken from the current draft
revision of the Declaration of Oslo.18
Editorial changes and additions to the 2016 proposal in all of the extracts
below are indicated by yellow highlight and red text respectively.
Sources
|
2018C/RDMA Proposal for WMA
|
|
9. There are several jurisdictions in
the world that through extensive democratic legislative processes,
court decisions and public debate have legalized certain forms of
euthanasia and assisted death under specific conditions.
|
The Canadian Medical Association supports the right of all
physicians, within the bounds of existing legislation, to follow
their conscience when deciding whether to provide medical aid in dying
as defined in CMA's policy on euthanasia and assisted suicide.[CMA Board Resolution (2014)]
|
The WMA does not support or sanction
euthanasia or physician assisted death,
but also does not condemn
or label as unethical
those physicians who follow their own conscience in deciding whether
or not to participate in these activities, within the bounds of
applicable legislation, in those
jurisdictions where euthanasia and/or physician assisted
death are legalized
and follow a person's voluntary and
well-considered request.
|
2. Termination of pregnancy is a medical matter between the patient and
the physician. Attitudes toward
termination of pregnancy are a matter of
individual conviction and conscience that should be respected.
[MEC 209/Therapeutic Abortion REV4/Apr2018]
|
Attitudes toward euthanasia and physician
assisted death are evolving and are a matter of individual
conviction and conscience that should be respected.
|
VI.4.3.2 Comparing the CMA Board Resolution and C/RDMA statements, two differences are apparent.
- The CMA
resolution was silent on the Association's position on euthanasia and
assisted suicide.
- The C/RDMA proposal clearly states that the WMA does
not support or sanction the procedures (though this is contradicted later).
- The CMA resolution affirmed support for the right of physicians to exercise freedom of conscience.
- The C/RDMA proposal states only that the WMA "does not condemn
or label as unethical" physicians who follow their consciences
concerning the procedures, and advocates respect for freedom of
conscience.
VI.4.3.3 Since the overwhelming majority of WMA members
would likely oppose any policy implying their support for the
euthanasia or assisted suicide, the explicit declaration to the contrary could be expected
to mollify them and minimize opposition to the C/RDMA proposal.
VI.4.4 Physician freedom of conscience
VI.4.41 The second recommended policy statement
directly addresses physician refusal to participate in euthanasia and assisted
suicide.
10. No physician should be forced to participate in euthanasia or
assisted death against their
personal moral beliefs. Equally, no physician should be forced to
refer a patient to another physician in
order to provide assistance in dying.
VI.4.4.2 The first sentence is essential
and sound, though "personal" is superfluous. At this point, demands
that physicians must personally provide euthanasia or assisted suicide are
only beginning to be made and are still rare.19,20
The distinction made between participation and referral is problematic, as
is the narrowing of protection to cases involving direct referral for the
procedures. These points are addressed in the detailed analysis in
Part VII.
VI.4.4.3 C/RDMA 2018 §11, the third policy statement, seeks to resolve conflicts
between patient demands for services and physician freedom of conscience,
including refusal to refer. It implies that the state or some other entity
is responsible for ensuring access to euthanasia and assisted suicide.
11. Jurisdictions that legalize euthanasia or physician assisted
death must provide mechanisms that
will ensure access for those persons
who meet the appropriate requirements. Physicians, individually or
collectively, must not be made responsible for ensuring access.
Where the law allows euthanasia
and physician assisted death to be performed, the procedure should
be performed by a competent physician or other health care provider.
VI.4.4.4 However, to state that physicians or health
care workers should provide euthanasia and assisted suicide where they are
legal flatly contradicts the earlier statement that the WMA "does not
support or sanction" euthanasia or assisted suicide (2018C/RDMA
§9).
VI.4.5 Palliative care
VI.4.5.1 A slight change in the preamble may indicate
that the CMA and RDMA do not believe that access to palliative care should be a precondition for the
provision of euthanasia and assisted suicide. (VI.3.13)
Changes in the fourth policy statement that deals directly with palliative
care seem consistent with
that conclusion.
12. WMA also calls on all
members to work to ensure access to high quality
palliative care services for those in need. Euthanasia and physician
assisted suicide should not be used as a substitute for palliative care
but should be seen as a last resort for those whose intractable and
hopeless suffering cannot be alleviated through any other ordinary means.
VI.4.5.2 The first change is subtle. The 2016
proposal stated that euthanasia and
assisted suicide "should never" be substitutes for palliative care,
but the 2018 proposal states they "should not" be (2018C/RDMA
s12).
VI.4.5.3 The second change is important but
invisible to readers who do not have the 2016 proposal. A key 2016 passage
has been struck from the 2018 version (§12 above).
VI.4.5.4 The deletion of the restriction resolves an
internal contradiction. The CMA and RDMA would have the WMA affirm that
patients have a right to the treatment they want, the right to determine the
manner and circumstances of their death, and the right not to be forced to
die "in ways they would not wish" (VI.3.2). However, if one accepts these rights
claims, to insist that euthanasia and
assisted suicide can be provided
only as a last resort, only in the face of intractable and
hopeless suffering would seem to be an unacceptable and paternalistic denial
of those rights. Striking out the requirement resolves the
contradiction and reinforces the claims.
Notes
1. World Medical Association. MEC
203/Euthanasia-Physician Assisted Dying/Apr2016: Proposed WMA
Reconsideration of the Statement on Euthanasia and Physician Assisted
Dying [2016 CDMA].
2. World Medical Association. MEC 210/Euthanasia and
PAD/Oct2018: Proposed WMA Reconsideration of the Statement on
Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Dying [2018 CDMA].
3.
World Medical Association.
Declaration of Venice on Terminal Illness [Internet].
2006 Oct [Cited 2018 Sep 29].
4.
World Medical Association.
Declaration on End-of-Life Medical Care
[Internet] 2011 Oct [Cited 2018 Sep 29].
5. Blackmer J Francescutti LH. Canadian Medical
Association Perspectives on End-of-Life in Canada. HealthcarePapers 2014
April;
14(1):17-20.doi:10.12927/hcpap.2014.23966
6. Grant K.
Medically assisted death allows couple married almost 73 years to die
together. [Internet]. 2018 Apr 1 [Cited 2018 Sep 28].
7.
Waterfield B.
Euthanasia twins 'had nothing to live for.' The Telegraph
[Internet] 2013 Jan 14 [Cited 2018 Sep 28].
8. Cook M.
Dutch couple choose euthanasia together. BioEdge [Internet].
BioEdge; 2017 Aug 19 [Cited 2018 Sep 28].
9. Murphy S.
Euthanasia reported in Belgium: statistics compiled from the Commission
Fédérale de Contrôle et d' Évaluation de l'Euthanasie Bi-annual Reports
[Internet]. Protection of Conscience Project; 2017 Aug [Cited 2018 Sep 29].
10. Murphy S.
Euthanasia reported in Netherlands: statistics compiled from the
Regional Euthanasia Review Committees' Annual Reports [Internet].
Protection of Conscience Project; 2017 Aug [Cited 2018 Sep 29].
11. Murphy S.
Assisted suicide reported in Oregon, U.S.A.: statistics compiled from
the Oregon Public Health Division annual Death with Dignity Act reports
[Internet]. Protection of Conscience Project; 2017 Aug [Cited 2018 Sep
29].
12. Murphy S.
Assisted suicide reported in Washington State, U.S.A.: statistics
compiled from the Washington State Dept. of Health annual Death with
Dignity Act reports [Internet]. Protection of Conscience
Project; 2017 Aug [Cited 2018 Sep 29].
13. For example, by August, 2017, Dr. Lonny
Shavelson of California was responsible for the deaths of 48 patients
pursuant to the state’s assisted suicide statute. See Nutik Zitter J.
Should I Help My Patients Die?
The New York Times. [Internet]. 2017 Aug 5 [Cited 2018 Sep 29].
14. Hune-Brown N.
How to End a Life. Toronto Life [Internet]. 2017 May 23 [Cited 2018
Sep 29].
15. First and second half year totals
=189+362=551. See Health Canada.
Interim update on medical assistance in dying in Canada June 17 to
December 31, 2016. Ottawa: Health Canada, 2017 [Internet]. Ottawa:
Health Canada, 2017 [Updated 2017 May 31; cited 2018 Sep 29].
Table 3.2: Profile of Medical Assistance in Dying by Jurisdiction/Region.
16. There were about 29,500 MDs in active
practice in the province. See College of Physicians and Surgeons of
Ontario.
2016 Annual Report [Internet]. Toronto: 2016 [Cited 2018 Sep 29] p. 7.
17. Blackmer J. Tweet Jeff Blackmer@jblackmerMD
[Internet]. Twitter;
2017 Nov 15 at 11:29 pm [Cited 2018 Sep 28].
18.
World Medical Association. MEC 209/Therapeutic Abortion REV4/Apr2018: Proposed WMA Statement on
Medically-Indicated Termination of Pregnancy (April, 2018).
19. Savulescu J, Schuklenk U.
Doctors have
no right to refuse medical assistance in dying, abortion or
contraception. Bioethics [Internet] 2017 [Cited 2018 Sep 29]
;31(3):162-170.
20. Attaran A. The Limits of Conscientious and Religious Objection to
Physician-Assisted Dying after the Supreme Court’s Decision in Carter v
Canada. Health L Can 2016; 36(3) 86-98.