Canadian/Royal Dutch Medical Association Proposed Change to WMA Policies
Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide
Full Text
X. PROJECT RECOMMENDATION
X.1 Conscience in the medical profession
X.1.1 Speaking in Jerusalem in 2016, WMA
Secretary General, Dr. Otmar Kloiber, drew attention to the expectation that
conscience will guide physicians in the practice of medicine, drawing from
that a lesson about the importance of freedom of conscience:
The Declaration of Geneva and the
International Code of Medical Ethics demand the physician to exercise
his or her profession with conscience. That, of course, is meaningless if a
conscientious objection is impossible. No physician must be forced to carry
out activities that are either deemed to be unethical altogether, like
participation in capital or corporal punishment, the force feeding of
prisoners or to perform services he morally cannot subscribe to.
In essence, physicians do not surrender their human
rights when becoming a physician. Not be coerced to provide certain
treatments is a matter of dignity and integrity for the physician as well.1
X.1.2 Consistent with Dr. Kloiber's remarks, Professor
David Oderberg of Reading University expands upon the role of conscience in
medicine in A Declaration in Support of Conscientious Objection in
Health Care:
In health care, conscience plays an essential role in
the professional judgment – often subtle and delicate – that practitioners
must exercise in their daily work. If health care workers are not to be
reduced to mere functionaries (of the state, of the patient, of the legal
system), they must be free to exercise their professional judgment and to
allow their consciences to inform that judgment. This freedom of
professional judgment informed by conscience must translate into the freedom
not to be involved in certain activities or practices to which there is a
conscientious objection.2
X.2 A broad and principled
approach
X.2.1 WMA policy documents occasionally refer
briefly to judgements of conscience, but it does not appear that the
Association has ever attempted to explain why conscience is central
to medical practice, or to connect this idea clearly to the exercise
of freedom of conscience. Further, all of the brief references to
the subject have been made within the context of
controversies associated with specific practices or issues.3,4,5,6
X.2.2 A significant shortcoming of
procedure-specific policy-making and legislation is that it is
inflexible. A policy or law that prevents coercion with
respect to abortion does not apply to artificial reproduction,
eugenic practices or human experimentation. Responding to
ethical controversies spawned by the rapid advance of medical
technology is especially challenging. It is not
practical for the WMA to spend one to three years developing
a protection of conscience policy applicable to a single procedure,
and repeat the process every time a new controversy arises.
X.2.3 Moreover, when policies are developed in
the midst of controversies about specific procedures or problems,
the policy response may be shaped by features unique to the
circumstances and prove problematic when considered in other
contexts. A special problem arises in the case of morally
contested procedures, when what ought to be judicious reflection on
freedom of conscience becomes entangled in partisan debates
about the acceptability of the procedures themselves. Opposing sides
in such debates may well come to see such policies merely as
strategic weapons to be turned to ideological advantage.
X.2.4 Conscience policies developed
in relation to specific procedures tend to foster and entrench a
morally partisan viewpoint, whether the viewpoint is that of a
dominant majority or a powerful minority. This leads to
discrimination,
either by allowing conscientious objection to some procedures, but
not others, or by imposing arbitrary and discriminatory limits on the exercise of
freedom of conscience: by, for example, allowing physicians to
refuse to refer for euthanasia, but forcing them to refer for
artificial reproduction.
X.2.5 For all of these reasons, it is preferable
to take a broad and principled approach that keeps the focus on the
nature and importance of freedom of conscience, avoiding
entanglement in controversies about the acceptability of morally
contested procedures.
X.3 Avoiding authoritarian "neutrality"
X.3.1 It is equally important to reject attempts
to impose authoritarian solutions masked by a pretence of
neutrality. For example, a theory of social contract professionalism
that has attained dogmatic status may be applied by those in power
to "resolve" moral issues by subordinating them to purportedly
neutral "professional" obligations. This approach is exemplified by
Udo Schuklenk and Julian Savulecu, who assert that "professionalism"
precludes conscientious objection.7,8
X.3.2 To claim, for example, that physicians act ethically or
with integrity only if they conform to professional expectations could be
taken to mean that "professional expectations" override the moral
agency and moral integrity of physicians. This is not a neutral
claim. Further, physicians may
disagree profoundly about whether participation in a given morally
contested procedure exemplifies adherence to or a violation of professional commitments: euthanasia is only the most recent and
obvious example. Hence, an attempt to regulate the exercise of
freedom of conscience by demanding conformity to a theory of
professionalism that fails to respect the moral agency of physicians will generate
unjust discrimination and exacerbate
rather than resolve conflict within the profession.
X.4 A stand-alone general protection of conscience policy
X.4.1 Assuming one avoids entanglement in
disputes about the acceptability of procedures/interventions, as
well as authoritarian "neutrality," a serviceable policy for protection of
conscience must be based on the understanding that recognition that
respect and protection of freedom of conscience serves the
fundamental good and dignity of the physician as a human person, not
merely professional autonomy or independence. It must include a number of basic features:
a) protection of the moral agency and
integrity of physicians by ensuring that they are not compelled to
do what they believe to be wrong, including
referral and other forms of close cooperation;
b) non-discrimination concerning physician
judgements of conscience, both as to the acceptability of a
procedure/intervention and decisions about participation or
non-participation;
c) an expectation that physicians will
provide patients with timely notice of deeply held beliefs that may
influence their recommendation or provision of
procedures/interventions the patient may request;
d) an expectation that physicians will
provide information necessary to enable a patient to make informed
decisions and exercise moral agency;
e) an expectation that physicians will
provide information to allow patient access to other physicians,
health care providers or the local, regional or provincial health
care system;
f) insistence that
objecting physicians cannot be expected and must not be made to assume
responsibility for ensuring access to procedures to which they object; the
state, other entities or non-objecting colleagues must assume that
responsibility.
Notes
1. Kloiber O.
Patients' Rights - A World View. The
Patients' Rights Act 20 years on – Achievements and Challenges.
Presentation at Peres Center for Peace, Jaffa, Israel. 2016 Jan 18
[Internet]. Protection of Conscience Project [Cited 2018 Sep 30].
2. Oderberg D. Declaration
in Support of Conscientious Objection in Health Care [Internet]. University of Reading; 2018
[Cited 2018 Sep 30].
Declaration, para. 2.
3. World Medical Association.
Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research
Involving Human Subjects [Internet]. 2008 Oct [Cited 2018 Sep 30]
para. 3.
4. World Medical Association.
Declaration of Malta on Hunger Strikers
[Internet]. 2017 Oct [Cited 2018 Sep 30] para. 17.
5. World Medical Association.
Declaration of Lisbon on the Rights of the Patient
[Internet]. 2015 Apr [Cited 2018 Sep 30] Preamble.
6. World Medical Association.
Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion
[Internet]. 2006 Oct [Cited 2018 Sep 30] para. 3.
7. Schuklenk, U. Why medical
professionals have no moral claim to conscientious objection
accommodation in liberal democracies. J Med Ethics 2017;43:234-240.
8. Savulescu J, Schuklenk U.
Doctors have no right to refuse medical assistance in dying, abortion or
contraception. Bioethics Bioethics [Internet] 2017 [Cited 2018 Sep
29] ;31(3):162-170.