Canadian/Royal Dutch Medical Association Proposed Change to WMA Policies
Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide
Full Text
IV. MEETINGS AND NEW PROPOSALS
IV.1 MEC and Council meetings (April, 2017)
IV.1.1 The Committee was advised of plans for the
conferences Tokyo in September and in Vatican City in November. It was also advised that a three day
WMA Ethics Conference would be held in conjunction with the WMA General
Assembly in Reykjavik, Iceland. The conference is to be open to the
public. At this stage, plans called for the second day of the Ethics
Conference to replace the usual scientific session of the General Assembly.
Denmark, Canada, Netherlands, Turkey, Kuwait, Brazil, CPME, Japan, Spain,
South Africa, Belgium, and the Chair of Medical Ethics Committee volunteered
to assist in developing topics for the conference.1
IV.1.2 Dr. Miguel Roberto Jorge of Brazil reported of that
the conclusions of the Latin American conference held the previous month had been endorsed by 14 national
associations. The Royal Dutch Medical Association (RDMA) claimed that some of the
conclusions in the report did not accurately reflect the situation in the
Netherlands. This presumably refers to mention of "the
phenomenon of the 'slippery slope' that has led in the Netherlands to its
application in people who had not requested it or did not meet the legal
requirements." The Belgian Medical Association stated that its regulations
were similar to the Dutch laws, but Belgium was not mentioned in the
report.2
IV.2 MEC and Council meetings (October, 2017)
IV.2.1 In an oral report to the Medical Ethics
Committee, the Secretary General described the end-of-life conference held
the previous month in Tokyo. He said that, with the exception
of Australia and New Zealand, "the appetite for discussing euthanasia and
physician assisted suicide in the Asia region is very low," and
that no medical association in the area supports the procedures.3
(The written report of the conference that would be received later states
that "all participants opposed euthanasia and physician assisted
suicide", apart from Zealand and Australia, there is "no appetite"
for discussion of the procedures in the region (III.3.4)
emphasis added).
IV.2.2 At the Council meeting in October, only a brief
and oblique reference was made to the organization of the regional
end-of-life conferences.4
IV.3 Canada and Netherlands on "assisted dying" in WM
Journal (October, 2017)
IV.3.1 The October issue of the World Medical
Journal included two lengthy articles on euthanasia and assisted
suicide, one by Dr. Jeff Blackmer about the CMA's approach to legalization
of the procedures,5 and the
other by two RDMA bioethicists, explaining and defending Dutch law and
practice.6
Notwithstanding disclaimers in both articles, they were written to support
the campaign by Canada and the Netherlands to change WMA policy, so it is
important to attend not only to what they emphasize, but what they leave
out.
IV.3.2 The Dutch bioethicists wrote in response to two previous
articles which, arguing for maintaining WMA opposition to euthanasia and
assisted suicide, had criticized the Dutch system.7,8 The
authors did not aim "to convince others or settle the debate" but
to correct "misconceptions" and to present alternative views worth
considering. Only points relevant to physician
freedom of conscience are considered here. Note that the term "euthanasia," as used by the
authors, includes assisted suicide.
IV.3.3 De Jong and van Dijt emphasize that euthanasia
remains a criminal offence if the criteria set out in the law are not
satisfied, that patients seeking it have no right to require physicians to
assist, and that physicians are "never obliged" to do so. For these
reasons they claim that euthanasia is neither a "therapeutic intervention"
nor "regular medical care,"9 and contrary assertions do
not reflect "the reality of the situation in the Netherlands."
IV.3.4 If all of this were really the case, it would be
most gratifying from the perspective of the protection of physician freedom
of conscience, for there would then seem to be no reason to insist that physicians
should
be involved in euthanasia and assisted suicide, no justification for
attempting to ensure their participation or collaboration, and no reason for
the WMA to change its policy. In point of fact, however, the RDMA does
consider euthanasia and assisted suicide to be therapeutic medical acts,
though not, as the authors correctly state, part of "regular" or
"standard" care.
A request for euthanasia is one of the most intrusive
and onerous demands that a patient can make of a physician. Most physicians
find it difficult to perform euthanasia or assisted suicide. This is all the
more true if that wish is not prompted by a terminal illness.10
IV.3.5 Nonetheless, the RDMA acknowledges (as the
authors do not) that the Dutch widely (though incorrectly) believe that they
have a right to euthanasia and assisted suicide from physicians, describing
this as "a common misconception."10 It also acknowledges
(as the authors do not) "burdensome" and "increasingly vocal" public
pressure to provide euthanasia to those with dementia and psychiatric
conditions and to "seniors who feel they have 'completed life,'" in response
to which the RDMA insists that "euthanasia is an exceptional medical
procedure that inherently entails a dilemma for the physician," and that
"plenty of physicians" are "unwilling or morally indisposed" to participate.11
Patients have the right to request euthanasia, but
physicians are not obligated to grant their request: fundamental objections
to euthanasia and assisted suicide must be respected. After all, euthanasia
and assisted suicide are anything but ordinary medical procedures.12
IV.3.6 Despite this, the RDMA demands that physicians
unwilling to kill patients or help them commit suicide or assisted suicide
must help them find a colleague willing to do so. "Though there is no
legal obligation to refer patients," it states, "there is a moral and
professional duty to provide patients with timely assistance in finding a
physician (for example, within the clinic) who does not have fundamental
objections to euthanasia and assisted suicide."12
IV.3.7 While the authors agree that physicians may be
morally obliged to provide euthanasia,13 many objecting
physicians emphatically reject the claim that physicians have a "moral duty"
to facilitate homicide and suicide under any circumstances, especially in
the absence of a legal requirement to that effect. That the RDMA
demands such collaboration, a critical point left out by the authors, is
surely relevant to any reconsideration of WMA policy on euthanasia and
assisted suicide. It is also relevant to evaluating the protection of
conscience provision in the CMA/RDMA proposal, which is contradicted by RDMA
policy on this point (VI.4.4.3,
VII.4.3.4).
IV.3.8 While it is true that euthanasia remains a
criminal offence if the criteria set out in the law are not satisfied, this
simply reflects the fact that it is not feasible to entirely abolish the law against
deliberate homicide; legalization of euthanasia entails making an
exception.
On this point, Canadian legislation is identical; non-consensual homicide
and assisted suicide remain criminal offences unless performed by a
physician in accordance with legal criteria,14 in which
case they are considered therapeutic medical interventions.15,16 That is
the basis for demands by some euthanasia advocates and regulators that Canadian physicians
must provide or facilitate the
procedures by referral.
IV.3.9 On the other hand, the authors identify an
important substantive
requirement of Dutch euthanasia law, but fail to appreciate its relevance to physician freedom of conscience. Dutch law requires
that the attending physician - not just the patient - must be satisfied that
the patient's suffering is unbearable, with no prospect of improvement, and
that there is "no alternative" to euthanasia or assisted suicide;17 the RDMA
insists that euthanasia must be literally a "last resort."9
These essential requirements for legality not being met, it would be a
criminal offence to facilitate euthanasia or assisted suicide by referral.
In most cases, objecting physicians would probably not agree that a
patient's suffering cannot be ameliorated, or that there is no alternative
to euthanasia. Thus, it would likely be impossible to successfully
prosecute an objecting physician for refusing to refer patients.
The Work of the Canadian Medical Association
IV.3.10 It is instructive to compare Dr. Blackmer's journal article
with details of the events as they unfolded (Appendix
"B"), filling in some details he omits and drawing attention to points
he does not develop.
IV.3.11 Dr. Blackmer describes the CMA Board of
Directors decision to actively shape the debate and law on euthanasia and
assisted suicide. His article discusses the CMA's internal and external consultation process,
the passage of a key policy resolution, its intervention in the Carter
case, and its activities following the decision and subsequent
legislation. He suggests that the WMA and other national associations should learn from the
CMA's example. In his view, there is no point in arguing about the
morality of euthanasia and assisted suicide because "no one is likely
to change their views on this." Rather, he says, it is better to
unite the medical profession in its approach to the procedures if they are
legalized.
IV.3.12 According to the Journal article, the CMA's
public consultation disclosed general agreement that access to palliative
and hospice care was important and that a national strategy was needed to
advance that goal, but that the public was divided on whether or not
euthanasia or assisted suicide should be legalized. The article
highlights agreement on the need for "strict protocols and safeguards" if
the law were changed, but does not make clear that this could only have been
supported by those uncertain about or in favour of legalization. It
also omits the finding that the potential impact of legalization on the
medical profession "should be carefully considered and studied further." (B3.3)
IV.3.13 The meetings with physicians confirmed the need
for advance care planning and palliative care. They also demonstrated that
euthanasia and assisted suicide were "no longer taboo subjects," that physicians were ready to discuss the subject
and even "lead the conversation", and what Dr. Blackmer describes as the
essential intractability of opinions about euthanasia and assisted suicide:
"No amount of argument or evidence was likely
to change anyone's mind."
IV.3.14 That is Dr. Blackmer's view: the report itself referred only to
the intractability of certain medical conditions, not physician opinions.18
Dr. Blackmer correctly states that it found "the
profession. . .divided on the issue of assisted death," but omits the fact
that the great majority of physicians - over 70% - were opposed to the procedures and a
change in CMA policy (B3.4).
IV.3.15 Dr. Blackmer highlights the policy resolution
adopted by the CMA's Annual General Council, which is especially
significant because it is very similar to the first of three WMA policy changes recommended by Canada and the Netherlands.
The Canadian Medical Association supports the right of all
physicians, within the bounds of existing legislation, to follow
their conscience when deciding whether to provide medical aid in dying
as defined in CMA's policy on euthanasia and assisted suicide.
IV.3.16 This is discussed in more detail in
Part
VI and VII and Appendix "B." For the
present, it is important to note that this did not lead the CMA to adopt a neutral position on assisted
suicide and euthanasia. The Board of Directors,
having convinced the delegates at the Annual General Council to approve an
ostensibly neutral resolution (B5.8,
B6.), later reversed CMA policy against
the procedures, formally approving both (subject to legal constraints) as
forms of "end of life care." Moreover, the policy committed the Association
to support euthanasia and assisted suicide as end-of-life care not only for competent adults,
but for any patient group and for any reason approved by the courts or
legislatures, including minors, the incompetent or the mentally ill (B9).19
IV.3.17 Legalization of euthanasia and assisted suicide has had serious adverse consequences
for objecting physicians (B10.5-9) that
are not mentioned in his Journal article.
He does not, for example, acknowledge that, as a direct consequence of the
reversal of CMA policy and legalization of the procedures, objecting
physicians have had to lobby the CMA for support and make "tearful pleas at
several CMA General Council meetings, asking their non-objecting colleagues
to support them and to defend their rights."20
IV.3.18 Dr. Blackmer states that,
after the Supreme Court of Canada ruling in Carter, "the CMA was tasked with
formulating a suggested legislative and regulatory approach to these complex
issues." What actually happened is that the federal government did
nothing for almost five months, then called (and lost) an election, leaving
the CMA and other stakeholders scrambling to develop policies without any direction as to what changes would be made to the
criminal law. The result was a policy and regulatory maelstrom that
lasted several months. The Board of Directors, having concentrated on
shaping the debate and changing CMA policy, was quite unprepared to mount a
cogent, articulate and persuasive defence of physician freedom of
conscience. (B10.19)
IV.4 MEC and Council meetings (April, 2018)
IV.4.1 The Medical Ethics Committee received four written reports
concerning the regional end-of-life conferences, supplemented by oral
reports from the Nigerian and German Medical Associations. The Secretary General
stated that the regional conferences were to lead to "an
international discussion" at the WMA Ethics Conference in Iceland in
October. This was the first indication in the minutes of the Medical
Ethics Committee that euthanasia and assisted suicide would be on the agenda
of the Ethics Conference.21
IV.4.2 It must have been clear to the Committee that virtually all
national associations that had participated in the regional conferences were
opposed to euthanasia and physician assisted suicide, and were presumably
satisfied with existing WMA policies. Moreover, while there was public
interest in New Zealand and Australia in legalizing the procedures, the
national medical associations in both countries remained opposed to
physician participation.
IV.4.3 The minutes disclose only that there was "further debate" about the subject.
According to the World Medical Journal, there was a brief
discussion about the fact that current WMA policy states that euthanasia is
unethical, but it has been legalized in some countries. The discussion
must have highlighted the difference between the ethical position of the WMA
and that of constituent medical associations like the CMA and RDMA. The committee
was told "there would be ample time to discuss this matter further at the
medical ethics conference in Reykjavik."22
IV.4.4 The Journal added another detail not recorded in
the minutes. The CMA and RDMA stated that they would be returning in
October with a revised proposal on euthanasia and assisted suicide "to see
if they could accommodate all the divergent views among members."22
IV.5 New proposal re: "Policy
Consistency" (3 July, 2018)
IV.5.1 In the first week of July, five associate
members submitted a policy proposal to be considered at the meeting of
associate members at the WMA General Assembly in October in Iceland.
The proposal is relevant to discussion at the April Medical Ethics Committee
meeting about inconsistency between WMA policy on euthanasia and that of
some of its constituent members (VI.4.3). One of
the five sponsors of the new proposal is a Canadian medical resident who
appears to have closely followed and frequently signalled approval of Dr.
Blackmer’s tweets from the conference in the Vatican (III.4.6
to III.4.21; III.4.28 to
III.4.30).
IV.5.2 In the preamble, the proposal states that it is
important that WMA and constituent member policies should, as far as
possible, be consistent with one another. It notes that, while WMA
policy development includes a review of national policies, a review of WMA
policy is less likely to happen during policy development by national
associations. The document proposes that policy development by national
associations should always include formal systematic consultation of WMA
policies.
IV.5.3 However, the proposal identifies "ethical
policy" as "a special case where consistency is most important and in
some circumstances may not be possible." Hence, while national medical
association policy "should be specific and consistent with World Medical
Association Ethical Policy," the sponsors argue that WMA ethical policies
should accommodate "national and culture differences."
When an NMA has an ethical opinion that is not
consistent with WMA policy, but is consistent with the law in its country
and is clearly generated by benevolence toward patients, WMA may allow for
national and cultural differences in formulating its own ethical policies.
IV.5.4 Euthanasia and assisted suicide are always described by EAS
advocates as expressions of benevolence or beneficence (within the present
context it is assumed the terms are interchangeable). Thus, if accepted,
the policy would force the WMA to "allow for" physician participation in
euthanasia and assisted suicide and even to allow for the coercion of
objecting physicians (VII.5.9).
IV.6 CMA & RDMA introduce revised
EAS proposal
IV.6.1 At the end of July the CMA and RDMA reintroduced
the proposal they had withdrawn previously, with revisions (Appendix
"C").
While they had stated that the revisions were intended to "accommodate
divergent views" among WMA constituent members (IV.4.4),
the only divergent views accommodated were those of the CMA, RDMA and other
EAS supporters, which diverge from the overwhelming majority of medical
associations around the world. The revisions are outlined below.
The revised proposal will be considered in detail in
Part VI.
Minor revisions
IV.6.2 Many of the revisions are minor. For
example, "assisted suicide" in the original is now "assisted death;" those
seeking the services were "patients" in the original but are "persons" in
the revised version. Some, like the definitions of
euthanasia and "assisted
death," are clarifications.23
A new section about the need to support for patients at the end of life is
unremarkable.24 The remaining changes
are rhetorical, rhetorical and substantive or substantive.
Rhetorical revisions
IV.6.3 There is special emphasis in the revised proposal on
democracy - "democratic processes" and
"extensive democratic legislative
processes" - and redoubled emphasis on legislation, court decisions and
public debate.25
IV.6.4 The most obvious rhetorical change reflects an
attempt to minimize the overwhelming opposition to euthanasia and assisted
suicide in the medical profession worldwide, amply demonstrated by the
results of the regional conferences. The admission that "the majority
of physicians" find the procedures to be irreconcilable with medical ethics
has been struck out entirely,
replaced with the statement that "many physicians" merely recognize a
conflict.26
IV.6.5 A new paragraph emphasizes a 'diversity'
of responses to this conflict. While it may reflect the associate members'
proposal introduced earlier in the same month (IV.5), it
is identical to a statement about abortion introduced into the revised
Declaration of Oslo that will be considered by the General Assembly in
October:27
Diverse responses to resolve this dilemma
reflect the diverse cultural, legal, traditional, and regional
standards of medical care throughout the world.28
Rhetorical and substantive revisions
IV.6.6 With respect to physician freedom of conscience,
the wording of the original proposal was very similar to the resolution used
by the CMA Board of Directors as the basis for reversing CMA policy against
euthanasia and assisted suicide (B5,
B6,
B7,
B9). A new paragraph
has been added, a slightly modified passage also taken from the revised
Declaration of Oslo.
Attitudes toward euthanasia and physician
assisted death are evolving and are a matter of individual
conviction and conscience that should be respected.29
At first glance, this seems
only to lend more weight to the emphasis on freedom of conscience.
IV.6.7 However, this is also a substantive change.
If attitudes toward euthanasia and assisted suicide continue to evolve, so
will the criteria for the procedures. All evidence to date
demonstrates that the evolution is exclusively in the direction of expanded
access, which generally speaking, entails increasingly controversial
criteria. If, as this statement requires, the WMA must respect all
attitudes toward euthanasia and assisted suicide no matter how they evolve,
the statement commits the WMA to accept euthanasia and assisted suicide for
any reason acceptable in law.
Substantive revisions
IV.6.8 With respect to EAS providers, the original
proposal stated that they were motivated by "compassion for their patients."
They are now said to be responding to "the immediate needs of their
patients."30 The change implies
an objectively verifiable need
to be killed or helped to commit suicide, so that by approving the
policy the WMA would acknowlede such a need.
IV.6.9 Palliative care was first said to be part of
"part of good and appropriate medical care," but in the revised proposal
this is only the case when it is "available."
The implication may be that actual access to palliative care need not be a
precondition for the provision of euthanasia and assisted suicide.31
Consistent with this, the original statement that euthanasia and assisted
suicide "should never" be substitutes for palliative care has been
revised to read that they "should not" be.32
IV.6.10 Originally, the CMA and RDMA proposed only that
the WMA affirm that it does not condemn EAS providers, but now wants the
Association to state, in addition, that they are
not acting unethically.33
IV.6.11 A new provision in the proposal states that
euthanasia and assisted suicide
should be provided by competent physicians or health care providers.34
If the WMA approves this proposal, it will not only reverse its policy
against the procedures, but affirm that, where the procedures are legal,
physicians have an ethical obligation to kill their patients or help them
commit suicide.
IV.6.12 The revised proposal
narrows the protection offered
to objecting physicians. The CMA and RDMA first stated that objecting
physicians should not be forced to refer patients to other physicians.
They now state that physicians should not be forced to refer "to another
physician in order to provide assistance in dying" (emphasis
added). This does not preclude compulsory referral to physicians who
will provide required consultations preliminary to lethal injection by
someone else, nor does it preclude compulsory referral to euthanasia
delivery coordinators.35
IV.6.13 Finally, in 2016, the CMA and RDMA insisted
that euthanasia and assisted suicide "should be seen as a last resort for
those whose intractable and hopeless suffering cannot be alleviated through
any other ordinary means."
This restriction has been struck out completely,36
indicating that the ultimate goal of the CMA and RDMA is the WMA's
unconditional approval of euthanasia and assisted suicide as legitimate
forms of medical treatment.
Notes
1. World Medical Association. MEC 206/Report/Apr2017: Report of the Medical Ethics Committee (20-21
April, 2017).
2. World Medical Association. Council 206/Minutes/Apr2017: Minutes of the 206th Council Session (20, 22
April, 2017) p.4.
3. World Medical Association. MEC 207/Report/Oct2017: Report of the Medical Ethics Committee (11
October, 2017) 3.10 Regional meetings on End-of-Life Question (EoL workshop),
p. 4-5.
4. World Medical Association. Council 207/Minutes/Oct2017: Minutes of
the 207th Council Session (11 and 13 October, 2011) p.2.
5. Blackmer J.
Assisted Dying and the Work
of the Canadian Medical Association. World Medical J [Internet]. 2017 Oct
[Cited 2018 Sep 29]; 63(3):6-9 [Blackmer-WMJ]
6. de Jong A, van Dijt G.
Euthanasia in the
Netherlands: balancing autonomy and compassion. World Medical J
[Internet].
2017 Oct [Cited 2018 Sep 29]; 63(3)10-15 [de Jong-van Digt].
7. Requena P.
Why Should the World Medical Association not Change its Policy towards
Euthanasia? World Medical J [Internet]. 2016 Oct [Cited 2018 Sep 29]; 62(3) 99-102 (Accessed
2018-05-31).
8. Keown J.
Voluntary Euthanasia and Physician-assisted Suicide: Should the WMA Drop
its Opposition? World Medical J [Internet]. 2016 Oct [Cited
2018 Sep 29];
62(3) 103-107(Accessed
2018-05-31).
9. Similarly, Herman Nys, writing in 2001:
"In the Netherlands the majority of health-care lawyers believe that
euthanasia is not a 'normal medical act', although it must be
administered by a physician. There is no medical indication for
euthanasia and there exists no professional medical standard for its
permissibility. Whether euthanasia is to be allowed or not is a matter
for society, not for the medical profession. The same is true of, say,
non-therapeutic abortion. Moreover, if euthanasia were a normal medical
act, the physician should in principle administer it. Nobody is of that
opinion in the Netherlands." Nys H.
Euthanasia in the low
countries: a comparative analysis of the law regarding euthanasia in
Belgium and the Netherlands. Ethical Perspect [Internet] 2002 [Cited
2018 Sep 29]; 9(2):73-85.
10. Royal Dutch Medical Association
[Koninklijke Nederlandsche Maatschappij tot bevordering der Geneeskunst
(KNMG)].
The Role of the Physician in the Voluntary Termination of
Life [Internet]. Utrecht, Netherlands:KNMG; 2011 Jun 23 [Cited
2018 Sep 29] [RDMA-Role of the Physician] p. 6.
11. RDMA-Role of the Physician, p.
6-7.
12. RDMA-Role of the Physician, p.
33.
13. ". . . the principle of compassion may
require physicians to grant such a request for euthanasia." de
Jong-van Digt, p. 15.
14.
Criminal Code. RSC 1985, c. C-46,
s 227,
241(2) to (5.1) [Internet] [Cited 2018 Sep 29]
15.
Doctor-assisted suicide a therapeutic
service, says Canadian Medical Association. CBC News, 6 February,
2016
(Accessed 2018-06-09).
16. The Canadian Medical Association
describes euthanasia and physician assisted suicide as "legally
permissible medical service[s]." Canadian Medical Association.
Medical Assistance in Dying
[Internet] 2017 May [Cited 2018 Sep 29] [CMA-MAID 2017].
17.
Dutch law on Termination of life on request and assisted suicide (complete
text) [Internet]. The World Federation of Right to Die Societies.
Termination of Life on Request and
Assisted Suicide (Review Procedures) Act [Cited 2018 Sep 29], 1(b)
and (d)
18. Canadian Medical Association.
End-of-Life Care: A National Dialogue. CMA Member Consultation Report
[Internet] 2014 Jul [Cited 2018 Sep 29][CMA Member Consultation] p. 8.
19. When the CMA revised the
policy in 2017, it reintroduced the distinction between euthanasia
and physician assisted suicide and other forms of end-of-life care.
CMA-MAID 2017.
20.
Blackmer J.
Letter
from Dr. Jeff Blackmer, Vice President, Medical Professionalism, Canadian
Medical Association, to Physicians' Alliance Against Euthanasia
[Internet]. Collectif des Médecins Contre L'Euthanasie; 2018 Apr 30 [Cited
2018 Sep28].
21. World Medical
Association. MEC 209/Report/Apr2018: Report of the Medical Ethics
Committee (27 April, 2018)
22.
Medical Ethics Committee, End of Life Questions. World Medical J
[Internet].
2018 Aug [Cited 2018 Sep 29]; 64(2):8-9.
23. World Medical Association. MEC
210/Euthanasia and PAD/Oct2018: Proposed WMA Reconsideration of the
Statement, Resolution and Declaration on Euthanasia and Physician
Assisted Dying [2018C/RDMA] §2. See also Appendix "C":
Comparison of 2016 and 2018 CMA/RDMA proposals [Appendix "C"]
Ref. E,
F.
24. 2018C/RDMA §13 (Appendix "C,"Ref. U)
25. 2018C/RDMA §1, 9 (Appendix "C,"
Ref. C,
N)
26. Compare MEC 203/Euthanasia-Physician Assisted
Dying/Apr2016: MEC 203/Euthanasia-Physician Assisted Dying/Apr2016: Proposed
WMA Reconsideration of the Statement on Euthanasia and Physician Assisted
Dying [2016 CDMA] §7 with 2018C/RDMA §8 (Appendix "C," Ref. K).
27. World Medical Association. MEC
209/ Therapeutic Abortion REV4/Apr2018: Proposed WMA Statement on
Medically-Indicated Termination of Pregnancy [Abortion Rev4], paragraph 3.
28. 2018C/RDMA §8 (Appendix "C," Ref. L)
29. 2018 C/RDMA, §8 (Appendix "C,"
Ref. P); compare Abortion Rev4, paragraph 2.
30. Compare 2016C/RDMA §1, with 2018C/RDMA §2
(Appendix "C,"
Ref. C)
31. Compare 2016C/RDMA §5, with
2018C/RDMA §6 (Appendix "C,"
Ref. H)
32. Compare 2016C/RDMA §10, with
2018C/RDMA §12 (Appendix "C,"
Ref. T)
33. Compare 2016C/RDMA§8, with 2018C/RDMA
§9 (Appendix "C,"
Ref. O)
34. 2018C/RDMA §11 (Appendix "C,"
Ref. S)
35. Compare 2016C/RDMA §9, with 2018C/RDMA §10
(Appendix "C,"
Ref. Q)
36. 2016C/RDMA §10 (Appendix "C,"
Ref. T)