Canadian/Royal Dutch Medical Association Proposed Change to WMA Policies
Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide
Full Text
IX. PROJECT RESPONSE
IX.1 Preliminaries
IX.1 It is one thing to limit freedom of conscience by
enacting laws that prevent people from doing everything that they want to
do. But to force people to do things that offend their conscientious
convictions cannot be reconciled with the best traditions and aspirations of
liberal democracy. It is, in principle, inconsistent with the most
rudimentary principles of civic friendship, a serious assault on the
essential foundation of fundamental freedom, and offensive to human dignity.
It is a fundamental injustice that cannot be rectified or ameliorated by
appeals to theories of justice or notions of equality.
IX.2 Thus, the Protection of Conscience Project,
without denying the importance of freedom of conscience in its widest sense,
restricts the scope of its activity to advocacy for freedom of conscience in
its most essential and foundational sense. Simply put, those providing
health care must not be forced to do what they believe to be wrong, or
punished for refusing to do so.
IX.3 The Project does not take a position on the
acceptability of euthanasia or assisted suicide. From the perspective
of the Project, legalization of euthanasia or assisted suicide or a change
of WMA policy against the procedures is of concern only to the extent that
legalization or change threatens to disadvantage or punish physicians who
refuse to do what they believe to be wrong.
IX.2 The issue
IX.2.1 If the CMA/RDMA proposal were accepted, would
it have adverse consequences for physician freedom of conscience?
IX.3 Relevant considerations
IX.3.1 Most physicians refuse
IX.3.1.1 The majority of
physicians believe participation in euthansia or assisted suicide is
irreconcilable with their ethical obligations. Available evidence
demonstrates
that the overwhelming majority of physicians worldwide are opposed to the
procedures and would refuse to participate (III.1.1),
and that, even where the procedures are legal, relatively few physicians are
directly involved in providing the services (VI.3.4). This
is not denied by the CMA and RDMA.
IX.3.1.2 Many physicians opposed to providing
euthanasia and assisted suicide are also opposed to facilitating or
collaborating in the procedures by referral or other means because they
believe that doing so makes them complicit in wrongdoing.
IX.3.2 Physician obligation to provide or facilitate
medical treatment
IX.3.2.1 Although euthanasia and assisted suicide can be provided by
non-medical personnel if authorized by law, when the law authorizes
physician administered euthanasia and physician assisted suicide, the
procedures are usually thought to be medical services or forms of medical
treatment, notwithstanding contrary views among those opposed to them. Medical associations that approve physician participation in the
procedures can be expected to take this position (IV.3.4,
VII.4.3.4,
B9.3,
B10.7).
IX.3.2.2 Physicians are understood to have an ethical
obligation to provide or facilitate access to medical treatment or services
needed by their patients. When professional or public authorities classify
euthanasia and assisted suicide as medical treatments, providing or
facilitating homicide and suicide becomes the norm, and refusal to do so the
exception that requires justification or excuse. (VII.4.2.3).
IX.3.2.3 Where the state undertakes to finance and
provide or arrange for the delivery of medical treatment, physicians may
come to be seen as state employees obligated to deliver or facilitate the
delivery of all legal medical treatments and services as a condition of
employment.1 This is complemented and supported by theories or models
of social contract professionalism.
IX.3.2.4 Since relatively few physicians are willing to
provide the services, patients must find a way to connect with willing
physicians. This leads to demands that objecting physicians faciliate
access by referral or other means (VII.4.3.4,
B.10.19).
IX.3.3 Rights claims
IX.3.3.1 The CMA/RDMA proposal asserts, by implication,
that people have a right to euthanasia and assisted suicide (VI.3.2,
VII.5.2). This
claim is increasingly common and consistent with the view that people have a
right to health care and medical treatment. Whatever the moral or
legal merits of such claims, they provide a basis for demands that
physicians provide or facilitate euthanasia.
IX.3.3.2 A more refined claim of a right to equitable
access to health care is made for the same purpose. When
joined to human rights laws prohibiting discrimination on the basis of
disability, the claim of a right to equitable access can ground a complaint
against a physician who provides euthanasia for the terminally ill, but not
for the clinically depressed. Hence, physicians who agree to provide
euthanasia or assisted suicide for one legally eligible patient may
find that they cannot legally refuse to provide the services for any legally
eligible patient, regardless of the condition or circumstances.2
IX.3.3.3 In either case, to seek to enforce these
claims with respect to euthanasia and assisted suicide would invoke the power of the state
to compel unwilling individuals to become parties to homicide and suicide,
and to punish or disadvantage them if they refuse.
IX.3.4 Likelihood of conflict
IX.3.4.1 The foregoing considerations indicate that
legalization of euthanasia and assisted suicide has the potential to cause
serious difficulties for the overwhelming majority of physicians who are
opposed to the procedures.
IX.3.4.2 Proportionate to death from all causes,
relatively few patients die from euthanasia and assisted suicide (VII.5.8).
However, everyone dies. Hence, where the procedures are legal, every physician in general practice and many
in other specialities may be confronted with a request for euthanasia or
assisted suicide, especially in specialties like oncology and palliative
care (VII.3.6.3). Everyone entering the medical profession will be faced with this
issue.
IX.3.4.3 Euthanasia and assisted suicide rates provide
some indication of the likelihood that objecting physicians will
encounter ethical conflicts with patients or colleagues where the procedures
are legal. However, the rate of requests for euthanasia and
assisted suicide is a more reliable indicator, since it is the need to
respond to a request for the procedures that may cause difficulties for
objecting physicians. Request rates are typically higher than
euthanasia/assisted suicide death rates.
IX.3.4.4 Generally speaking, the broader the grounds
for euthanasia and assisted suicide, the greater the likelihood that
conflicts of conscience will arise. For example: physicians willing to provide the services in the last days
of a terminal illness may not be willing to provide them for chronic
depression.
IX.3.4.5 Generally speaking, the wider the range of
people legally entitled to authorize euthanasia, the greater the likelihood
of conflicts of conscience. For example: physicians willing to provide euthanasia
at the request of competent patients may not be willing to provide
euthanasia at the request of a family member for someone with dementia who
is not otherwise ill.
IX.4 Response to the issue
IX.4.1 It is reasonable to believe that the CMA/RDMA
proposal would, if accepted, encourage the legalization of physician
administered euthanasia and physician assisted suicide around the world (VII.5.7).
IX.4.2 The proposal posits a right to euthanasia and
assisted suicide that is unrestricted with respect to eligibility criteria
and other conditions under which they might be provided. For example, it
does not limit provision of the procedures to terminal illness, does not
preclude the procedures as a response to mental illness, disability, or
chronic medical conditions, and does not require access to palliative care
as a prerequisite. It does not limit provision of the services to adults:
adolescents, children and infants are not excluded. It does not
exclude euthanasia of incompetent patients authorized by advanced directives (VII.2.4).
IX.4.3 To the extent that legalization does occur in accordance with
the proposal, particuarly in view of its unrestricted scope, the overwhelming majority the world's physicians
represented by WMA members would be exposed to demands that could generate serious conflicts
of conscience and ultimately place
those unwilling to provide or cooperate in providing the services in
serious professional jeopardy (IX.3.1.1,
IX.3.4.4, X.3.4.5 ).
IX.4.4 The protection of conscience provisions
in the proposal do not afford sufficient protection for objecting
physicians, especially in light of the increased probability of conflict due
to the virtually unrestricted scope of the proposal. The provisions are not
well-grounded and actually rejected by one of the co-authors of the
proposal (VII.4).
IX.4.5 The experience of objecting physicians in Canada
demonstrates that the WMA should not follow the example of the CMA by
precipitously changing its policy without sufficient reflection and
forethought.3
IX.4.6 Given the particular gravity of the
consequences of invoking state power against objecting physicians with
respect to participation in homicide and suicide, the WMA should not change
its policy on euthanasia and physician assisted suicide without first
establishing a sound and robust policy to protect physician freedom of
conscience.
IX.4.7 However, a sound policy concerning physician freedom of
conscience cannot be developed within the narrow perspective afforded by
controversies about particular procedures. The Project recommends, instead,
a broad and principled approach be taken to develop a single protection of
conscience policy.
Notes
1. Dr. Preston Zuliani (President of the
College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario, Canada's largest state
medical regulator). "In our society, we all pay for this medical
system to receive services. And if a citizen or taxpayer goes to
access those services and they are blocked from receiving legitimate
services by a physician, we don't feel that's acceptable." Laidlaw
S. Does faith
have a place in medicine? Toronto Star [Internet]. 2008 Sep 18
[Cited 2018 Sep 29]. The College now demands that objecting
physicians provide "effective referrals" for all services, including
euthanasia and assisted suicide, notwithstanding their moral or
religious beliefs (VII.4.3.3).
2. "[I]f a doctor willingly prescribes
pain-relieving drugs to alleviate suffering - for arthritis,
back
pain, cancer, stomach ulcer, et cetera - but selectively refuses to
prescribe secobarbital
or pentobarbital to a patient who lawfully
chooses to die, that differential denial of service
(i.e.,
prescribing vs. not prescribing) needs a satisfactoryjustification, or
it is discriminatory and illegal." Attaran A. The Limits of
Conscientious and Religious Objection to Physician-Assisted Dying after
the Supreme Court’s Decision in Carter v Canada. Health L Can 2016;
36(3) 86-98 at 87.
3. Murphy S.
Canadian Medical
Association and euthanasia and assisted suicide in Canada: Critical review
of CMA approach to changes in policy and law [Internet].
Protection of Conscience Project; 2018 Sep 26 [Cited 2018 Sep29].