Project Logo

Protection of Conscience Project

www.consciencelaws.org

Service, not Servitude
Ethics

Proposed Change to WMA Policies
Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide

VI.    REVIEW OF THE CMA/RDMA PROPOSAL

"The CMA accepts that the decision of whether or not medical aid in dying should be
allowed as a matter of law is for lawmakers, not medical doctors, to determine. The policy itself acknowledges, uniquely among CMA policies in this respect, that "[ilt is the prerogative of
society to decide whether the laws dealing with euthanasia and assisted suicide should be
changed."  In the SCC on appeal from the BCCA, Factum of the Intervener, The Canadian Medical Association (27 August, 2014) [CMA Factum] para. 5.

"In any event, the CMA accepts that the decision as to the lawfulness of the current
prohibition on medical aid in dying is for patients and their elected representatives as lawmakers to determine, not physicians." CMA Factum, para. 17.

Blackmer J.  Assisted Dying and the Work of the Canadian Medical Association.  World Medical Association Journal. 2017 Oct; 63(3):6-9 [Blackmer-WMJ) (Accessed 2018-05-24).

Dr. Chris Simpson, CMA Annual General Council, August, 2015. Session: Setting the Context for a Principles Based Approach for Assisted Dying in Canada (video) 0:01:45-0:01:55

Downar J, Bailey M, Kagan J, Librach LS.  Physician-assisted death: time to move beyond Yes or NoCMAJ 2014 May 13; 186 567-568; DOI: https://doi.org/10.1503/cmaj.140204 (Accessed 2018-06-15).

"The question of neutrality has been profoundly obscured by the mistake of confusing neutrality with objectivity... neutrality and objectivity are not the same... objectivity is possible but neutrality is not. To be neutral, if that were possible, would be to have no presuppositions whatsoever. To be objective is to have certain presuppositions, along with the manners that allow us to keep faith with them." Budziszewski J. "Handling Issues of Conscience." The Newman Rambler, Vol. 3, No. 2, Spring/Summer 1999, P. 4.

8.  World Medical Association Revision of WMA Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion (2006), Appendix "D": Mandatory Referral - From Abortion to Euthanasia

 

VII.5    Arguments offered
Rights claims

VII.5.1    The sole justification offered for the change is that patients "must be free to decide for themselves what treatments they want and the manner and circumstances of their death and may not be forced to die in ways they would not wish."(VI.3.4). 

VII.5.2    This justification, proposed as if self-evident, actually consists of contested autonomy based rights claims that have grave implications for physicians, inasmuch as they imply a professional obligation to kill (VI.3.5, VI.3.6, B10.5).  To accept contested rights claims as sufficient justification for the proposal would disenfrancise those who hold contrary views.

Neutrality, limited effect

VII.5.3    The proposal is presented as a kind of neutral option that does not require the WMA to support euthanasia or physician assisted suicide, does not involve significant change, and would affect only physicians legally providing the services by relieving them of accusations of unethical conduct.

VII.5.4    However, the proposed change is not ethically neutral. Notwithstanding the opening disclaimer, which is a bare and inefficacious assertion that has no necessary ethical significance (VI.4.5, VI.4.6), it implies that euthanasia and assisted suicide are consistent with medical ethics, or at least not so inconsistent as to preclude them being provided by physicians, even if ordinarily inadvisable (VI.4.5, VI.4.10).

VII.5.5     Certainly, the foundational statement would prevent the WMA from condemning Dutch or Canadian physicians who provide euthanasia or assisted suicide for unethical conduct, which, according to the CMA, is the sole reason for seeking the change (III.4.3, III.4.11, VII.1.2). 

VII.5.6    However, the change in position signified by the foundational statement would also have worldwide implications because it would entail a meaningful ethical shift by an international opinion leader.  It could reasonably be expected to influence physicians, other healthcare workers, the public and lawmakers around the world in favour of the procedures  (VII.3.6.4, VII.3.6.5).

VII.5.7    Moreover, the completely unrestricted nature of the foundational statement (VII.1.3, VII.1.4, VII.1.7) commits the WMA to tolerating the legalization and practice of euthanasia and assisted suicide on the broadest possible terms.

Patient priority

VII.5.8    Patient priority, autonomy, and the importance of compassion are widely understood to be central to medical practice, and the CMA's Dr. Francescutti alluded to this when he warned the WMA Council that they "would not serve their patients well" by refusing to heed public opinion about assisted suicide (VII.3.4.1).  Upon these grounds, those uncertain about the morality/ethics of the procedures are likely to give the benefit of their uncertainty to patients clearly seeking the services and physicians willing to provide them by supporting legalization and by referring patients to willing colleagues (VI.3.4.3).

VII.5.9    However, even if one accepts principles of patient priority, autonomy and the importance of compassion, it does not follow that one must conclude that euthanasia and assisted suicide are morally/ethically acceptable, or that the moral/ethical nature of the practices is uncertain.  Philosophical, moral or ethical arguments to the contrary can be rationally advanced and defended without denying patient priority and the need for compassion (VI.3.4.2, B8.2). 

Pragmatism

VII.5.10    What has been said of patient priority, autonomy, and compassion is also true of other principles like respect or reverence for human life, beneficence, non-maleficence and justice.  Positions for and against euthanasia and assisted suicide, when firmly held and rationally defended, usually rest upon different interpretations or understandings of such principles. 

VII.5.11    Dr. Blackmer describes such differences as the problem of intractability (IV.3.13-14), which the CMA and RDMA urge the WMA to solve by setting them aside (VII.3.5).  "T]he way forward," Dr. Blackmer says, "is not to engage in further debate on the rightness or wrongness of assisted dying,"4 but, as CMA President Dr. Chris Simpson put it, to  "[move] away from a yes-no dichotomy, as to whether assisted dying should be legalized toward a more balanced and nuanced discussion."5

VII.5.12    While urging the WMA to take this path forward, Dr. Blackmer does not say where the path leads.  Dr. Simpson suggests it leads to "a more balanced and nuanced discussion," but does not say what the discussion is about.  The answer is found in an editorial in the Canadian Medical Association Journal: Physician-assisted death: time to move beyond Yes or No.  "Whether or not physicians individually or collectively agree with physician-assisted death," wrote the autors, "[i]t is time for the "yes" or "no" debate to give way to a constructive dialogue about policies and guidelines for legal physician-assisted death," including such things as eligibility, consent, equitable access, effective methods, and the obligations of conscientious objectors.6 

VII.5.13    In other words, the CMA and RDMA want moral and ethical debate about physician participation in euthanasia and assisted suicide to end, and practical discussion about how physicians should provide the services to begin.  This seems to be what the CMA meant when it suggested the WMA consider "a more nuanced approach" to assisted suicide (II.1.2). 

VII.5.14    Dr. Blackmer's "way forward" is to nullify continued opposition on moral/ethical grounds.  Dr. Simpson provides balance and nuance to the "yes" or "no" debate by eliminating the "no." The CMA approach exemplifies what Project Advisor Jay Budziszewski calls "bad faith authoritarianism . . . a dishonest way of advancing a moral view by pretending to have no moral view."7

VII.5.15    In this case, "unreflective" may be more fitting than "dishonest."  In any case, without reference to ethics of some sort, the WMA cannot follow Dr. Blackmer's advice to decide how to respond to legalization of physician assisted suicide and euthanasia.  The CMA did not set ethics aside when it purported to unite the Canadian medical profession behind the view that euthanasia and physician assisted suicide can be legitimate forms of medical treatment (B9) - hardly an ethically neutral viewpoint.  Later the CMA did, indeed, delete references to ethical and even medical criteria from its policy on euthanasia and assisted suicide (VI.4.25), but this means only that the CMA has chosen the law as its ethical standard, not that it has dispensed with ethics altogether.

Disagreement/lack of consensus

VII.5.16    The appeal to pragmatism is the CMA/RDMA reaction to what they perceive to be an obstacle created by particularly stubborn disagreement or lack of consensus, an obstacle to be bypassed by the assumption that their moral/ethical viewpoint is correct.  Can they  plausibly cite lack of consensus, not as an obstacle, but as a reason to support their proposal? (VII.3.7.1, VII.3.7.2)

VII.5.17    This seems unlikely, since the CMA/RDMA proposal itself is based upon contested rights claims for which no consensus exists (VII.2.1, VII.2.2).  Further, the argument is not tenable for two practical reasons.

VII.5.18    First: the result of the four regional meetings provides evidence that, at least with the WMA, there is a consensus that euthanasia and assisted suicide are morally or at least ethically unacceptable (III.1.2).  Thus, the CMA and RDMA can appeal, at best, only to the fact that some physicians disagree with the WMA, and the mere existence of disagreement within an organization does not warrant a change of policy. 

VII.5.19    Second: WMA ethics policies are based, not on lack of consensus, but upon a consensus identified by 75% approval (VII.3.7.4).  The CMA and RDMA may eventually succeed in achieving this, or they may succeed in convincing the WMA that the standard should be changed to make it more likely that their proposal will be accepted (VI.3.7.5) but have not yet done so.

VII.6    Conclusions

VII.6.1    Justification offered for the proposal rests upon contested rights claims.

VII.6.2    The opening disclaimer of non-support for euthanasia and assisted suicide is a bare and inefficacious assertion that has no necessary ethical significance.

VII.6.3    Notwithstanding the opening disclaimer and arguments offered, the CMA/RDMA proposal, if accepted, would substantially shift WMA policy in favour of legalization of euthanasia and physician assisted suicide in accordance with the proposal.  It would commit the WMA to tolerating the legalization and practice of euthanasia and assisted suicide on the broadest possible terms.

VII.6.4    The shift in WMA policy in accordance with the proposal would not exclude physician provision of euthanasia and assisted suicide for

  • any legally valid reason, including non-terminal chronic conditions or disabilities, even in the absence of pain or suffering
  • any class of patients defined by law, including adolescents, children and infants, and incompetent and mentally ill patients.

VII.6.5    The shift in WMA policy in accordance with the proposal

  • would not require the provision of adequate palliative care as a prerequisite for euthanasia and assisted suicide, and
  • would not preclude the provision of euthanasia and assisted suicide as alternatives to palliative care and ordinary medical treatment.

VII.6.6    The shift in WMA policy could reasonably be expected to cause physicians, other healthcare workers, the public and lawmakers around the world to favour legalizing the procedures in accordance with the proposal.

VII.6.7    The shift in WMA policy in accordance with the proposal would make legislatures and courts responsible for establishing ethical and legal criteria for euthanasia and assisted suicide.

VII.6.8    The protection of conscience provision is generally commendable.  However, it is insufficiently developed to withstand challenges it is likely to meet in practice.  It is not actually supported by one of the authors of the proposal.

VII.6.9    The argument that the irreconcilable moral/ethical debate about euthanasia/assisted suicide should be solved by setting moral/ethical issues aside is manipulative and self-contradictory.

VII.6.10    An argument supporting the proposal by an appeal to lack of consensus would be inconsistent with the sole justification offered for it, for which there is no consensus.  It would also conflict with the WMA standard for identifying consensus.

 

VI.5    Effects

VII.1.4    Were the WMA to adopt the recommended policy statements, it would unconditionally affirm the acceptability of euthanasia and assisted suicide on the broadest terms.  This would encourage legalization of the procedures, jeopardizing freedom of conscience for the majority of physicians in affected jurisdictions.

 

 

VI.4.20     While the protection of conscience provison is generally commendable, the rationale supporting it is not articulated or clear from other WMA policy. Given the challenges it will face, it is not at all certain that it would actually provide adequate protection for physicians.  In fact, the RDMA, one of the authors, already contradicts it by demanding that objecting physicians refer patients for euthanasia, even though Dutch law does not require it (IV.3.6).

 

VI.4.18    While this is a sound approach, and the protection of conscience provision is generally commendable, it has been rejected by Canada's largest medical regulator.

VI.4.19    This reflected the effects of a sustained campaign to compel physicians to refer for other morally contested services like abortion, which, in effect, has been a dress rehearsal to compel them to refer for euthanasia and assisted suicide.  The reasoning used to justify the former is also used to justify the latter. This is abundantly clear from the Canadian experience.23 The College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario imposed mandatory referral for all morally contested services except euthanasia and assisted suicide in 2015,24 and extended the policy to include euthanasia and assisted suicide in 201625 because "there was no qualitative difference" between euthanasia and assisted suicide "and other health care services."26

VI.5.1   

The CMA and RDMA foresee no effects flowing from the change of WMA policy on euthanasia and assisted suicide, but "speaking points would need to be prepared for elected leaders in the case of public/media interest."  This is an exceptionally unrealistic assessment of the consequences of accepting the proposal and the level of interest that it would attract.  The adoption of a very similar motion by the CMA was widely considered to be an "overwhelming change;" the CMA president called it a "sea change," even before the CMA Board of Directors reversed Association policy against the procedures (B7.11).  Analogous changes to WMA policy on capital punishment (VI.4.8) or female genital mutilation (VI.4.9) would be seen as major policy changes that would have a significant impact on medical practice in many countries, and would attract enormous attention worldwide.

VI.4.12    In Canada, euthanasia and assisted suicide are available for psychiatric patients suffering from other irremediable disorders, and (as Dr. Blackmer acknowledges) the possibility of providing euthanasia and assisted suicide for mature minors and as a therapeutic intervention to relieve suffering caused by psychiatric disorders and dementia is being considered. Recall that de Jong and van Dijt admit that euthanasia can be provided in the Netherlands for those with dementia and psychiatric diseases, and even for those with whom the physician "cannot communicate adequately," though they say the latter cases are rare and "highly controversial."18 

 

VI.5.3    According to then CMA President Dr. Chris Simpson, the CMA had learned from studying other jurisdictions that legalizing assisted suicide and euthanasia led to "changes in the medical culture" so that "there is general, overall comfort" with the law. "And where it works best, of course, and where it is the case everywhere as far as I’m aware," he said, "is that only physicians who have particular expertise in, in doing this and, and have a moral and ethical framework that allows them to do it is where it works well."34

VI.5.4    Legalization of euthanasia and assisted suicide and the accompanying change of "medical culture" would expose the overwhelming majority the world's physicians represented by WMA members to demands that could generate serious conflicts of conscience and ultimately place those unwilling to collaborate in serious professional jeopardy.  This is the case in Canada, where physicians in some provinces face discipline and even expulsion from the profession if they refuse to refer patients for the procedures.25

 

the CMA is asking the WMA to follow its example by entrusting legislatures and courts with responsibility for legalizingand establishing the medical and ethical criteria for euthanasia and assisted suicide (B9.4, VI.4.24),1,2  even at the cost of moral angst among physicians (B10.11) and at the risk of unpredictable results (B10.11, B10.12) beyond the control of the medical profession (B10.13).

 



Notes

1.    World Medical Association.  MEC 203/Euthanasia-Physician Assisted Dying/Apr2016: Proposed WMA Reconsideration of the Statement on Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Dying [2016 CDMA].

2.    World Medical Association.  MEC 210/Euthanasia and PAD/Oct2018: Proposed WMA Reconsideration of the Statement on Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Dying [2018 CDMA].

3.    WMA Declaration of Venice on Terminal Illness.  Adopted by the 35th World Medical Assembly, Venice, Italy, October 1983 and revised by the 57th WMA General Assembly, Pilanesberg, South Africa, October 2006  (Accessed 2018-06-02).

4.    WMA Declaration on End-of-Life Medical Care. Adopted by the 62nd WMA General Assembly, Montevideo, Uruguay, October 2011  (Accessed 2018-06-02).

5.    Blackmer J Francescutti LH. Canadian Medical Association Perspectives on End-of-Life in Canada. HealthcarePapers 2014 April; 14(1):17-20.doi:10.12927/hcpap.2014.23966

6.   

7.    Murphy S. Euthanasia reported in Belgium: statistics compiled from the Commission Fédérale de Contrôle et d' Évaluation de l'Euthanasie Bi-annual Reports. Protection of Conscience Project. August, 2017.

8.    Murphy S. Euthanasia reported in Netherlands: statistics compiled from the Regional Euthanasia Review Committees' Annual Reports. Protection of Conscience Project. August, 2017.

9.    Murphy S. Assisted suicide reported in Oregon, U.S.A.: statistics compiled from the Oregon Public Health Division annual Death with Dignity Act reports. Protection of Conscience Project. August, 2017.

10.   Murphy S. Assisted suicide reported in Washington State, U.S.A.: statistics compiled from the Washington State Dept. of Health annual Death with Dignity Act reports.  Protection of Conscience Project. August, 2017.

11.   For example, by August, 2017, Dr. Lonny Shavelson of California was responsible for the deaths of 48 patients pursuant to the state’s assisted suicide statute. See Nutik Zitter J. Should I Help My Patients Die? The New York Times. 5 August, 2017 (Accessed 2017-08-23).

12.    Hune-Brown N. How to End a Life. Toronto Life. 23 May, 2017. Accessed 2017-08-29.

13.    First and second half year totals =189+362=551. See Health Canada, Interim update on medical assistance in dying in Canada June 17 to December 31, 2016. Ottawa: Health Canada, 2017: Table 3.2: Profile of Medical Assistance in Dying by Jurisdiction/Region (Accessed 2017-10-09).

14.    There were about 29,500 MDs in active practice in the province. See College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario. 2016 Annual Report. Toronto: p. 7 (Accessed 2017-10-03).

15.    Jeff Blackmer@jblackmerMD (15 November, 2017 at 11:29 pm) (Accessed 2018-05-15).

16.    World Medical Association.  MEC 209/ Therapeutic Abortion REV4/Apr2018: Proposed WMA Statement on Medically-Indicated Termination of Pregnancy (April, 2018).

17.   

18.   

19.    de Jong A, van Dijt G. Euthanasia in the Netherlands: balancing autonomy and compassion. World Medical Ass J. 2017 Oct 63(3)10-15 (Accessed 2018-05-24).Savulescu J, Schuklenk U. Doctors have no right to refuse medical assistance in dying, abortion or contraception.  Bioethics 2017;31(3):162-170 (Accessed 2018-06-04).

20.    Attaran A. The Limits of Conscientious and Religious Objection to Physician-Assisted Dying after the Supreme Court’s Decision in Carter v Canada. Health L Can 2016; 36(3)  86-98.

21.    Murphy S.  Canadian Medical Association and euthanasia and assisted suicide in Canada: Critical review of CMA approach to changes in policy and law.  Part I: Preliminaries to Carter - A professional obligation to kill.  Protection of Conscience Project (September, 2018).

22. 

23.    See World Medical Association, Revision of WMA Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion (2006): Appendix "D" -  Mandatory Referral - From Abortion to Euthanasia.

24.    College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario.  Professional Obligations and Human Rights (March, 2015), p. 5 (Accessed 2018-06-13).

25.    College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario. Medical Assistance in Dying (July, 2017) (Accessed 2018-06-13).

26.    The Christian Medical and Dental Society of Canada v. College of Physicians and Surgeons of Ontario, 2018 ONSC 579 (Can LII), para. 169, p. 33 (Accessed 2018-06-15).

27.    In the SCC on appeal from the BCCA, Factum of the Intervener, The Canadian Medical Association (27 August, 2014).

28.    Geddes J. Interview: The CMA’s president on assisted dying. Macleans, 6 February, 2015 [Geddes] This part of the interview is not included in the edited published transcript, but can be heard on the linked audio file (02:43-03:25) (Accessed 2018-06-04).

29.    Canadian Medical Association. Medical Assistance in Dying (May, 2017) [CMA-MAID 2017] (Accessed 2018-06-01).

30.    "The CMA recognizes that it is the prerogative of society to decide whether the laws dealing with euthanasia and assisted suicide should be changed." Canadian Medical Association, CMA Policy: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide (Update 2014) (p. 3).

31.    Dr. Blackmer, referring to the Supreme Court decision ordering the legalization of euthanasia and physician assisted suicide, said, "Many doctors do not like the decision and that is OK, but ultimately it is society, through its elected representatives and courts that is making these rules and decisions. Basically, the profession is saying OK, whether you agree with this or not, the SCC has ruled, so the time for that discussion has passed and now we need to make sure that we help the government get it right."  Santi N.  From Courtroom to Bedside - A Discussion with Dr. Jeff Blackmer on the Implications of Carter v. Canada and Physician-Assisted Death.  UOJM 2015 May; 5(1) (Accessed 2015-07-04).

32.    "The judicial and legislative branches of government have made changes to Canadian law in this area. Society has placed assistance in dying within the realm of regulated medical practitioners." CMA-MAID 2017, p. 1.

33.   

Geddes.

 

Print Friendly and PDF