Protection of Conscience Project
Protection of Conscience Project
www.consciencelaws.org
Service, not Servitude

Service, not Servitude

World Medical Association

Revision of WMA Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion (2006)

12 December, 2017

Sean Murphy*

Introduction

This commentary has been prepared at the request of an Associate Member of the World Medical Association for the use of WMA Associate and Constituent Members, and members of national physicians' associations that are Constituent WMA Members.  The original WMA documents quoted and cited herein are available on the WMA website.

Full Text
Download PDF
Abstract

Almost all members of the World Medical Association (WMA) were satisfied with a minor revision of the WMA’s 2006 Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion circulated for comment in 2016. Nonetheless, a WMA Working Group has proposed a new abortion policy (WGAP). A WMA Associate Member has asked the Protection of Conscience Project to review the policy.

The WGAP has serious adverse implications for physicians who, for reasons of conscience, refuse to provide abortion. The 2006 Declaration states that they "may withdraw while ensuring the continuity of medical care by a qualified colleague." This ensures continuity of care without requiring facilitation of abortion by referral or other means. The provision was unchanged in the Secretariat Revision and acceptable to almost all WMA members.

In contrast, the WGAP requires objecting physicians to refer patients for abortion, even if they believe that referral is unethical. It is incoherent to assert that physicians are ethically obliged to do what they believe to be unethical, and many objecting physicians consider referral unacceptable.

The WGAP requirement is not supported by the returns from even the handful of members who commented on the Secretariat Revision. Only one suggested a minor revision, and none recommended compulsory referral.

Further, to force objecting physicians to facilitate what they believe to be unethical or immoral procedures would be inconsistent with other WMA statements and policies that explicitly prohibit physicians from doing so.

Moreover, as demonstrated by developments in Canada, the WGAP provides a precedent for compelling unwilling physicians to refer for other morally contested procedures, including euthanasia, assisted suicide. It can also be cited to support demands that physicians personally perform such procedures.

Finally, the Working Group ignored or failed to notice the distinction between therapeutic and elective abortion drawn to its attention by responding WMA members. The distinction is essential to identifying a physician’s ethical and professional obligations concerning abortion. However, the WGAP is ambiguous on this point, and controversial because it can be cited to support the claim that physicians must provide or refer for elective abortions.

The WGAP should be rejected. It is subversive of physician freedom of conscience concerning abortion in the short term, and euthanasia and assisted suicide in the long term. On the other hand, the 2006 Declaration could be safely reaffirmed with the update to Clause 5 proposed by the Working Group.


TABLE OF CONTENTS
I.    BACKGROUND
II.    WORKING GROUP ABORTION POLICY AND CONSCIENCE
III.    OTHER ELEMENTS OF THE WORKING GROUP ABORTION POLICY
IV.    SUMMARY
V.    CONCLUSION
 

APPENDIX "A"
Abortion: 2006 Declaration and Secretariat Revision
APPENDIX "B"
National Association Responses to the Secretariat Revision
APPENDIX "C"
Working Group Abortion Policy
APPENDIX "D"
Mandatory Referral - From Abortion to Euthanasia
D1.    Canadian Medical Association
D2.    Mandatory referral for abortion revisited
D3.    Mandatory referral for euthanasia proposed
D4.    Mandatory referral for abortion, euthanasia and assisted suicide
D5.    Mandatory physician provision of abortion and euthanasia
APPENDIX "E"
Therapeutic and Elective Abortion

I. BACKGROUND
I.1    The World Medical Association

I.1.1     The World Medical Association (WMA) is comprised of 115 national medical associations (constituent members)1 that are "broadly representative of the physicians in their countries," which are "not subject to, or controlled by, any office or agency of government."2

I.1.2    In addition, individual physicians may become associate members. The associate members form a group analogous to a national association. They may vote in an Annual Associate Members Meeting and, through their chosen representatives, participate (but apparently not vote) in the WMA General Assembly.2 As will be seen, the associate members' group may also be consulted by standing committees and the WMA executive about policy development.

I.1.3     The WMA is organized in six regions: Africa, Asia, Europe, Latin America, North America and the Pacific.3 Its working languages are English, Spanish and French.

I.1.4     The WMA Council is the executive of the organization, the members of which are elected every two years by the WMA General Assembly. Members of the Council are drawn from the six WMA regions.3 The Council meets twice yearly, in the spring and in autumn. After the Council meeting in autumn, delegations from all constituent members assemble in the General Assembly, "the supreme decision-making body of the WMA."4

I.1.5     The WMA has three standing committees: Medical Ethics, Finance and Planning, and Socio-Medical Affairs.3

I.1.6     The Secretary General of the WMA is the chief executive officer of the organization and the head of the Secretariat, full time administrators in Ferney-Volataire France.3

I.2    Policy review: abortion
WMA Secretariat Revision

I.2.1     The WMA has an annual policy review process. In April, 2016, the Council decided that the 2006 WMA Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion should be reaffirmed with minor revisions. In October, the Secretariat submitted a draft revision of the Declaration for consideration by the Council (Secretariat Revision - SR).5 With one exception, the revisions were purely editorial (Appendix "A").

I.2.2    The 2006 Declaration observed that a conflict may arise between the interests of a mother and her unborn child in some circumstances, raising the question of abortion (Clause 2). It acknowledged a "diversity of responses" in such situations was partly due "to the diversity of attitudes towards the life of the unborn child," adding, "This is a matter of individual conviction and conscience that must be respected." (Clause 3)6

I.2.3     The Secretariat did not change the text of these clauses, but moved and recombined them in such a way that, in the Secretariat Revision, "This is a matter of individual conviction and conscience that must be respected" (Recommendation 2) was made to refer, not to "the life of the unborn child," but to the requirement that physicians "maintain respect for human life."(Recommendation 1)5

I.2.4     This change was subtle and not inconsistent with the original, since "respect for human life" can pertain to the lives of both mother and unborn child. In its new position, "respect for conviction and conscience" about "respect for human life" may have been intended to avoid attributing greater importance to the life of the unborn child.

I.2.5     In any case, this was the only modification of any significance. The substance of the 2006 Declaration remained intact in the Secretariat Revision (Appendix "A"). In October, 2016, the Council decided to circulate the Secretariat Revision to WMA members for comment.7

I.2.6     The Secretariat Revision was returned with comments from 15 of 116 members (115 constituent members and the associate members' group), which suggests that the overwhelming majority of associations were satisfied with the document. Of the 15 associations that offered comments, only four suggested significant revisions (Appendix "B"). However, because of "controversies of opinions" reflected in the returns from these associations, the Secretariat suggested that the Council should appoint an individual or group to further discuss revisions to the Declaration.5

Working Group Abortion Policy

I.2.7     The Medical Ethics Committee met in April, 2017. 18 members were present.8 Dr. Heidi Stensmyren of the Swedish Medical Association was elected chair. It was decided to refer the Secretariat Revision to a working group consisting of volunteers from Australia, South Africa, Canada, together with committee facilitator, Professor Vivienne Nathanson. Dr. Stensmyren encouraged others to participate.9

I.2.8     The working group (ultimately consisting of representatives from South Africa, Australia, Denmark, Korea, and Dr. Joseph Heyman, Chair of Associate Members)10 reported back to the Medical Ethics Committee in October, 2017. Of the 18 Ethics Committee members present, most had been at the previous meeting.11 The working group chairman, Dr. Seleao Mametja of the South African Medical Association, provided an oral report and submitted the group’s draft revision [Working Group Abortion Policy (WGAP)].

I.2.9     Dr. Mametja said that the working group had met just before the meeting of the Medical Ethics Committee "and proposed additional adjustments to the document" as well as a change of the name of the document from "therapeutic abortion" to "medically indicated abortion." The Ethics Committee recommended that the WGAP be circulated to WMA members for comment.12

Policy change timeline

I.2.10     The WGAP was circulated to national associations for feedback at the end of November. Responses from the national associations were requested by 12 February, 2018.10

I.2.11    It would seem that feedback received by 12 February will provide the basis for the next report on the WGAP, which will presumably be made at the Council Meeting in April, 2018. The Council could, at that time, recommend that the WGAP be adopted and put the document on the agenda for the General Assembly, which meets on 3-6 October, 2018 in Reykjavik, Iceland.7

WMA Medical Ethics Conference, 2018

I.2.12     From 2-4 October the WMA will hold a major ethics conference in Reykjavik in conjunction with the General Assembly. It will be open to the public. Belgium, Brazil, Canada, Comité Permanent des Médecins Européens (CPME13), Denmark, Japan, Kuwait, Netherlands, Turkey, South Africa, Spain, and the Chair of the Medical Ethics Committee have volunteered to participate.14 A website for the conference is already active.15

I.2.13    The usual Scientific Session of the General Assembly is to be replaced by the second day of the ethics conference, which "will focus on important topics for the WMA."15 This would provide an ideal opportunity to convince delegates to adopt new policies on abortion and euthanasia.

II.    WORKING GROUP ABORTION POLICY AND CONSCIENCE

II.1     The overwhelming majority of WMA members - 100 out of 116 - appear to have been satisfied with the Secretariat Revision. Further, the Working Group was formed because of "controversies" among the handful of WMA members who did comment on the Secretariat Revision (Appendix "B").

II.2    These circumstances do not suggest a need for a radical change of policy concerning a controversial issue.  However, the Working Group does propose a radical change to WMA policy (Appendix "C").

II.3    Compulsory referral

II.3.1    Clause 6 of the 2006 Declaration, carried over unchanged in Clause 5 of the Secretariat Revision, states:

If the physician's convictions do not allow him or her to advise or perform an abortion, he or she may withdraw while ensuring the continuity of medical care by a qualified colleague.

II.3.2    This does not imply that a physician is obliged to facilitate abortion by referral or other means. It has been the Project’s experience that objecting physicians are quite willing to continue medical care for the patient that does not include abortion, or to arrange for a colleague to do so.

A duty to do what is believed to be wrong

II.3.3     In contrast, the WGAP requires physicians who refuse to provide abortion for reasons of conscience to refer patients to someone who will, even if they believe that referral is unethical because it makes them morally complicit in what they believe to be gravely wrong. In short, the WGAP relies upon the incoherent premise that there can be an ethical obligation to do what one believes to be wrong.

II.3.4    Many objecting physicians, accepting the concept of vicarious moral/ethical responsibility, believe that they can be morally responsible for acts committed by another person. Hence, an undetermined number of physicians who object to abortion for reasons of conscience (either in principle or in a particular case, such as sex selection) would also object to facilitating abortion by referral.

Not justified by WMA member responses

II.3.5     Among the fifteen responding members, 12 left the protection of conscience clause intact (SR Recommendation 5), and one (the American Medical Association) recommended only minor clarifications of the provison. Neither the French nor the British indicated an intention to suppress physician freedom of conscience in relation to elective abortions. Only one medical association in the world - Sweden - clearly sought the suppression of physician freedom of freedom of conscience in relation to all abortions (Appendix "B").

II.3.6     In sum, the requirement for referral introduced by the Working Group cannot be justified by reference to the returns from the fifteen responding members.

Inconsistent with WMA policies

II.3.7    The concept of vicarious moral/ethical responsibility, which makes referral unacceptable for many objecting physician, is accepted by the World Medical Association. It is applied in the Statement on Organ and Tissue Donation16 and its resolutions prohibiting physician participation in capital punishment,17,18 torture and interrogation.19 All of these prohibit physicians from even indirectly facilitating conduct by others that contradicts principles of medical ethics. 

II.3.8    The point here is not that abortion is morally equivalent to capital punishment or torture, but that one who believes that X is wrong does not act unreasonably by refusing to facilitate X.  If it is reasonable for the WMA to accept and apply this principle, it is equally reasonable for objecting physicians to do so, and to refuse to facilitate abortion by referral or other means.

II.3.9     Moreover, the Declaration of Geneva explicitly states that physicians must practise medicine "with conscience and dignity,"20 and the WGAP itself asserts that "individual conviction and conscience [about abortion] . . . must be respected" (Clause 2). The WMA would contradict the Declaration of Geneva were it to respect the consciences of physicians willing to refer for abortion, while overriding the consciences of those unwilling to do so.  This would amount to a policy of discrimination based on ethical orientation.21  The Canadian Medical Association has dealt squarely with this issue in an eloquent submission to a Canadian medical regulator:

For the majority of physicians who will choose not to provide assistance in dying, referral is entirely morally acceptable; it is not a violation of their conscience. For others, referral is categorically morally unacceptable; it implies forced participation procedurally that may be connected to, or make them complicit in, what they deem to be a morally abhorrent act. In other words, referral respects the conscience of some, but not others.22

Preliminary to compulsory referral for euthanasia

II.3.10     Notice that this submission concerned mandatory "effective referral" for euthanasia and assisted suicide. What most national associations probably do not realize is that forcing physicians to facilitate abortion is preliminary to forcing them to facilitate euthanasia, assisted suicide or any other morally contested procedure. The reasoning used to justify the former is also used to justify the latter. This is abundantly clear from the Canadian experience (Appendix "D").

Preliminary to compulsory physician provision of abortion, euthanasia

II.3.11  Moreover, most constituent and associate members of the WMA probably do not realize that, ultimately, forcing objecting physicians to refer may not satisfy those who demand that physicians participate in morally contested acts. Once it is accepted that objecting physicians can be compelled to refer for morally contested procedures, it can be argued that they should be compelled to perform them, since referral makes them complicit in the act in any case. Those unwilling to personally provide abortion and euthanasia should not become physicians. Once more, this is demonstrated by the Canadian experience  (Appendix "D").

II.4    Therapeutic and elective abortion

II.4.1    The Working Group either ignored or did not recognize an issue raised explicitly by the Netherlands and implicit in the comments of other responding associations: the distinction between "therapeutic" and "elective" abortion (Appendix "E", E1.).

II.4.2    A therapeutic abortion to be one performed to save women’s lives or to prevent serious, permanent injury to them (Appendix "E", E2.). An elective abortion is one performed for socio-economic or other reasons, including birth control (Appendix "E", E3.).

II.4.3    Replacing "therapeutic" with "medically indicated" is not helpful because the terms are not equivalent. "Medically indicated" can refer to both therapeutic and elective abortions. The WGAP would, if adopted, mean quite different things in different parts of the world, and would be used to justify coerced provision or referral for elective abortions, notably those provided for birth control (Appendix "E", E4.).

II.4.4    This is significant because the majority of abortions in North America and the United Kingdom (and probably in other developed countries where the procedure is widely available) are not therapeutic. They are overwhelmingly elective abortions performed for the purpose of birth control (Appendix "E", E5, E6.).

II.4.5    However, there is a significant difference between an act of birth control by contraception and an act of birth control by killing an embryo/fetus/unborn child. It is reasonable for women and their physicians to incorporate this into their moral reasoning, even if they ultimately arrive a different conclusions concerning the moral acceptability or need for elective abortion. The killing of her embryo/fetus/unborn child may be particularly important or advantageous for a woman making the request.  It does not follow, however, that reasons she finds sufficient to justify her own acts are sufficient to compel physicians who think differently to kill her embryo/fetus/unborn child, or to punish them if they refuse (Appendix "E", E7.).

II.4.6     Granted the profound impact of pregnancy and childbirth on a woman and the need to respect her bodily and personal integrity and moral agency, objecting physicians have an equal claim to protection from violation of their bodily and personal integrity and moral agency (Appendix "E", E8.).

II.4.7    Attempts to suppress physician freedom of conscience with respect to abortion frequently employ the paradigm of "therapeutic" abortion. That is: it is said that physicians must be compelled to provide or refer for all abortions because abortions are performed only to save the life of the mother or to prevent serious permanent injury. This is the premise underlying the WGAP demand for referral. As returns comments from the Netherlands and others indicate, the premise is demonstrably false.

II.4.8    A physician’s ethical and professional obligations to provide elective procedures cannot be reasonably construed as being identical to their obligations to provide emergency medical treatment. It is disingenuous to purport to "balance" physician freedom of conscience with patient access to abortion without taking this into account.

II.4.9    Unfortunately, the Working Group did not take this into account, and, moreover, replaced the existing protection of conscience provision with a passage that is ambiguous on this very point (C2.3.13). Hence, its policy is likely to cause more controversy because it is likely to be used to force physicians to provide and facilitate elective abortions for non-medical socio-economic reasons and birth control (Appendix "E", E9.).

III.    OTHER ELEMENTS OF THE WORKING GROUP ABORTION POLICY
III.1    Deletion of respect for human life

III.1.1    The deletion of the requirement that physicians maintain respect for human life was not suggested by any member of the WMA outside the Working Group (Appendix "C", C2.1).

III.2    Clauses 2-3: Abortion as a medical act / no maternal relationship

III.2.1    The assertion that abortion is a "medical matter" admits no exceptions. Hence, the paragraph implies that sex-selective abortion is a purely "medical matter," contradicting the WMA Resolution on Female Foeticide (Appendix "C", C2.2.5-8).

III.2.2    Consistent with the deletion of the requirement for respect for human life, the WGAP now requires respect for attitudes to abortion, not (as in the 2006 Declaration) to the life of the unborn child/fetus, or (as in the Secretariat Revision) to human life. This is a subtle but significant change (Appendix "C", 2.2.6).

III.2.3    The statement that abortion concerns only the "patient" (singular) and physician effectively excludes the view that abortion concerns three individuals, or that a physician treating a pregnant woman has two patients. Replacing the terms "mother" and "unborn child" with "woman" and "fetus" erases the concepts of maternity and maternal relationship, as well as the equal humanity of mother and child (Appendix "C", C2.2.9-12).

III.3    Clause 4: Law and social policy

III.3.1 While suggesting advocacy by physicians and national associations concerning abortion, the paragraph makes no reference to adequate prenatal, obstetric or maternal health care, nor to advocating health policies that ensure such care is available (Appendix "C" C2.3.1-2).

III.4    Clause 5: Technical standards

III.4.1    This clause satisfactorily incorporates comments from responding members. It recognizes that abortion can be provided by health care workers who are not physicians, and more thoroughly articulates the corresponding provision in the 2006 Declaration (Appendix "C", C2.3.3).

III.5    Clause 6: Convictions of doctors and patients

III.5.1    While this new clause affirms that the "convictions" of both a doctor and patient must be "respected," this is not equivalent to an affirmation that moral, ethical, or religious convictions must be respected, nor to an affirmation that freedom of conscience and religion must be accommodated (Appendix "C", C2.3.4-7).

III.6    Clause 7: Patients with moral convictions

III.6.1    The new clause states that "patients with moral convictions"must have appropriate support and "necessary medical and psychological treatment." None of the responding members made a recommendation to this effect. Since all patients have moral convictions, and all most be provided with necessary treatment, the statement is redundant or meaningless (Appendix "C", C2.3.7).

III.7    Clause 9: Availability of "therapeutic abortion services"

III.7.1    It appears that this statement is intended to ensure that abortion service is made a priority during famines, droughts, natural and man-made disasters and in war zones.

III.7.2    While the clause urges advocacy to ensure that no woman dies because of lack of therapeutic abortion services, no comparable advocacy is urged with respect to the need for adequate prenatal, obstetric or maternal health care, nor to advocating health policies that ensure such care is available.

III.7.3    Granted the importance of preserving the lives of pregnant women, it is remarkable that, among the many policies, declarations and resolutions produced by the World Medical Association, there is not a single one devoted to the provision of prenatal and maternal health care, and the sole document concerning obstetric care is the Declaration on Therapeutic Abortion (Appendix "C", C2.3.17-19).

III.8    General

III.8.1    Clauses 4, 5, 7 and 9 do not appear to be problematic from the perspective of freedom of conscience, although the advocacy recommended in Clauses 4 and 9 is clearly biased in favour of abortion.

III.8.2    Clause 6 is misleading because it actually does not require that freedom of conscience be accommodated, and it is contradicted by the demand for compulsory referral in Clause 8.

III.8.3    The deletion of the requirement to respect human life and the addition of clauses 2 and 3 do not directly affect freedom of conscience. However, taken together with the new demand to respect attitudes toward abortion (rather than life), the changes are prejudicial to the position of physicians who hold that abortion involves two individuals/patients, who acknowledge that pregnancy involves a maternal relationship, or who insist that the lives of both the woman and her unborn child/fetus have the same value in ethical calculations.

III.8.4    Hence, the general tenor of the WGAP demonstrates a bias in favour of abortion and against the exercise of freedom of conscience by physicians who refuse to participate in abortion for reasons of conscience. This bias must also be considered in assessing the impact of Clause 8, which is directly concerned with freedom of conscience.

III.8.5    Note that the Working Group’s elimination of respect for human life and replacement of evocative words like "mother" and unborn child" with the minimally demanding technical terms "fetus" and "pregnant woman" did not produce an unbiased document. It simply changed the bias.

IV.    SUMMARY

IV.1    The WGAP is a radical revision of the 2006 Declaration of Oslo on Therapeutic Abortion not called for by the overwhelming majority of WMA members. It demonstrates a general bias in favour of abortion and against physician freedom of conscience. The demand for mandatory referral is not supported by the comments of the few members who commented on the Secretariat Revision of the Declaration.

IV.2    The Working Group claims that physicians are ethically obliged to facilitate abortion by referral, even if they believe that doing so is unethical or immoral. This claim is incoherent, since there can be no ethical obligation to do what one believes to be wrong.

IV.3    To force objecting physicians to facilitate what they believe to be unethical or immoral would contradict the Declaration of Geneva. It would also be inconsistent with WMA statements concerning organ and tissue donation, capital punishment, torture and interrogation, all of which prohibit physicians from even indirectly facilitating conduct by others that contradicts principles of medical ethics. Finally, adopting the WGAP would signal the support of the WMA for discrimination based on ethical orientation.

IV.4    The distinction between therapeutic and elective abortion is essential to identifying a physician’s ethical and professional obligations concerning the procedure. The Working Group not only failed to acknowledge the distinction, but replaced the existing policy with a passage that is ambiguous on this very point. Hence, the WGAP, if adopted, would likely cause more controversy, since it would usually be applied in order to compel physicians to facilitate elective abortions for the purpose of birth control.

IV.5    Forcing physicians to facilitate abortion is preliminary to forcing them to facilitate other morally contested procedures, including euthanasia, assisted suicide, and, ultimately, to personally providing such services. This would drive many physicians from medical practice and close the medical profession to many religious believers and others whose philosophy of medicine reflects a traditional Hippocratic approach.

V.    CONCLUSION

V.1    The WGAP should be rejected. It is subversive of physician freedom of conscience concerning abortion in the short term, and euthanasia and assisted suicide in the long term.

V.2    On the other hand, the 2006 Declaration could be safely reaffirmed with the update to Clause 5 proposed by the Working Group. which is clearly supported by the returns from the handful of WMA members who commented on the Secretariat Revision.